FROM PROPERTY TO PERSON: THE CASE OF EVELYN HART

By Lee Hall and Anthony Jon Waters.

© 2000 by Seton Hall Constitutional Law Journal; Lee Hall and Anthony Jon Waters.

Dear visitor,

We (Lee Hall & Tony Waters, then a new graduate and a professor from the University of Maryland School of Law) published this 22 years ago as a model Supreme Court brief that could support the expansion of Constitutional personhood to nonhuman animals. Contrary to what we’d hoped, society hasn’t changed its view of animals as nonpersons in all these years. People are still making the arguments in court, and, as our model brief did, they use some form of proof of a being’s cognitive capacities to make their case for personood.

This model brief, inspired by the Great Ape Project of the 1990s, points to sentience as the basis for taking nonhuman interests seriously, but, like the Great Ape Project, also throws a lot more cognitive proof into the case. I no longer believe arguments based on cognitive capacity are relevant to animal liberation, or that acquiring legal personhood in court is relevant to animal liberation. I no longer believe we ourselves, regardless of expert status, have the capacity to assess other beings’ awareness of their experiences on Earth. And when they’ve attempt to do so, thereby creating the field known as cognitive ethology, the experts have intruded on or entirely destroyed the lives, privacy, and freedom their research subjects ought to have had.

In 1997-2000 (the time it took to write this brief), I was learning from, and doing volunteer work for, people who think about cognition, not liberation. I still find the case for nonhuman personhood interesting. I’d like it to suceed, to the extent that it acknowledges habitat, and not human-controlled settings, as the real locus of nonhuman interests. Yet today my focus is on defending that habitat and pressing for human respect of whole, interconnected bio-communities.

Global heating makes the holistic, ecosystem-based call for liberation visibly urgent. In many regions of the globe’s surface, whole communities of sentient beings, and the life they’ve co-evolved with and depend on, are breaking down. In short, we don’t have time to go into court, name one species at a time, and tell judges about the complex abilities and rich senses of a particular member of that species. It would take forever to expand any progress in court to where it really needs to go.

When progress is real, we stop thinking in terms of line-drawing around species. We stop making other living beings prove they have respect-worthy interests. We defend habitat. We learn how to control ourselves, and transcend our infamous human avarice.

The enslavement of human and nonhuman beings is, as this brief shows, interwoven. Race discrimination sprang from a concept that some human beings should be regarded as other species, and that a natural hierarchy justified mastership. The results, described in this brief, were serial, systematic atrocities. The unfreedom, the torture, the loss of intergenerational culture, and the profound and persistent toxicity of disrespect will never be fully accounted for, let alone redeemed. Nor can humanity ever recover what was lost through such colossal wrongs. But solid respect for fair treatment of the personhood of all human beings, which law courts are at least partly equipped to promote, calls for reparations.

The orginal citation to the article is: Hall, L., & Waters, A. J., From Property to Person: The Case of Evelyn Hart, 11 Seton Hall Constitutional Law Journal 1-68 (2000). Footnotes can be found under the text. This republication is dedicated to the memory of Tony Waters—to whom, I regret, I did not get a chance to say a proper goodbye.

— Lee Hall, in the week of Earth Day, 2022.


PREFACE: THE PURPOSE OF THIS BRIEF

This article is about the legal category “person.” Personhood brings with it all manner of rights and protections. Human beings, for the most part, are persons; but not so long ago in this country, some were while others were not. Corporations, too, are relative newcomers to personhood and they, of course, are persons for some purposes, but not for others. Corporations were accorded limited personhood because it suited the capitalist system. Up to a point. Thus, corporations can be criminally liable but cannot be incarcerated; they must pay taxes, but cannot vote.

The legal category of persons never has been fixed or static, and is not now limited to human beings.

We humans understand the other great apes much more completely than was possible even a few years ago.*1* We now know that chimpanzees, gorillas, bonobos, and human beings are all species of African great apes. Together with orang-utans, we are members of a slightly larger taxonomic group known as the great apes, or “hominoidea.”*2*

Not only do we have a new understanding of our biological kinship with the other great apes, but we have also gained an awareness about their complex emotional and social repertoires. This knowledge brings with it an ethical and constitutional issue which is fundamentally important to the system of values which informs and animates our society and, hence, our law. That issue is whether we can, in good conscience, maintain the legal distinction between persons and nonpersons by drawing a bright line around human beings (and a few of their creations), to the absolute exclusion of all others. More specifically, this Brief addresses the question whether the Constitution of the United States ought to accommodate non-human great apes by affording them the rudimentary protections afforded other persons.

The concept of personhood serves a dual function: “it helps to protect those considered persons against suffering the hurts and indignities that the selfish tendencies of human psychology could inflict on them, and it helps to justify treating those creatures not considered persons selfishly.”*3* To classify certain beings as persons is to grant them moral and legal rights which protect them from being treated as nothing but a means to human satisfaction. To deny such rights is to permit such beings to be used as property, or creatures of nature existing for the sake of human satisfaction. Our law currently views most beings as fitting into one of these two categories: persons with constitutional rights or items of property.

The laws of the United States place non-human great apes on the “property” side of the line that divides persons from property. Such classification parallels the Cartesian view*4* of all non-human living beings as machinery. Yet modern knowledge indicates that volition versus mechanical response is not a dichotomy but a continuum.*5*

The non-human hominids present compelling reasons for our law to move beyond the legal dichotomy that divides “persons” from “property.” The plaintiff in this Brief argues that if only two categories exist in the modern legal mind, she belongs in the category of “persons” for the purpose of the constitutional protections whose benefits she now seeks. The term “non-human rights” may sound odd or at least unfamiliar, but, as was explained in a famous legal essay, “each time there is a movement to confer rights upon some new ‘entity,’ the proposal is bound to sound odd or frightening or laughable. This is partly because until the rightless thing receives its rights, we cannot see it as anything but a thing for the use of ‘us’—those who are holding rights at the time.”*6*

Whenever humans have considered extending the scope of personhood, fear of the consequences has emerged as the prime argument for not doing it. John Stuart Mill asked: But was there any domination which did not appear natural to those who possessed it? …So true is it that unnatural generally means only uncustomary, and that everything which is usual appears natural. The subjection of women to men being a universal custom, any departure from it quite naturally appears unnatural.*7*

Because the property classification treats non-human apes as instruments, tools, and toys, their interests can be protected only by reclassifying them as persons. Our present knowledge about their abilities compels this reclassification. In 1997, the British Parliament acknowledged this when it announced a ban on invasive experiments on chimpanzees and other hominids. Lord Williams of Mostyn said, “This is a matter of morality. The cognitive and behavioural characteristics and qualities of these animals means it is unethical to treat them as expendable for research.”*8* Thus a government has officially decided that the nature and capacities of certain non-humans demand that we no longer be entitled to treat them as property. This, without regard to any benefit to humans that might result from doing so.

On October 8, 1999, the New Zealand Parliament introduced, through the Animal Welfare Act, a prohibition of the use of all non-human great apes in research and testing, unless such use is in the best interests of the subject or her species.*9* This marks a dramatic change in the status of non-human hominids: they cannot be treated as research tools, to be used for the benefit of humans.

One potentially daunting aspect of extending rights anew is logistical. Often, these logistical problems have been given as reasons for opposing the recognition of the rights of a given group. But solutions to practical problems have often evolved only after society had determined to chart a new legal course. The history of school desegregation offers an example of this phenomenon. Moral and legal progress in the United States has enabled this society to overcome deep-seated prejudices, and to develop practical solutions to difficulties arising from the new social landscape. Furthermore, one salient factor should temper any concerns about the practical consequences of recognizing the rights of great apes. Free-living apes, or those in their natural habitats, do not attempt to invade our societies: it is we who invade and disrupt theirs, thus creating the problem.*10*

In this Brief we argue that our new knowledge of great apes mandates the protection of their fundamental interests by our legal system. Both those individuals living in captivity, and those still in their native environment*11*—whose greatest need is simply to be let alone—are entitled to protection. Specifically, this Brief addresses the plight of non-human great apes in the United States, all of whom are living outside of their native environment.*12* It presents the case of a chimpanzee whose human guardian contests an order dispatching her to a government-funded biomedical research laboratory. The story of Evelyn Hart is a composite; Hart personifies every non-human great ape who is sold into human commerce. The cases and resources cited in footnotes are actual. The constitutional issues concern the actions of the state of Georgia and of the National Institutes of Health, a federal entity. Both entities now support invasive research on non-human great apes. Therefore, this Brief considers the application of constitutional law on a federal level, as well as its application to a state through the Fourteenth Amendment.

“Although the Constitution is a legal document,” writes Professor Cass Sunstein, there will be a great deal of opportunity to adapt constitutional meaning to changes in both understanding and practice over time. Words are outrun by circumstances. They may be rendered ambiguous by the sheer passage of time. New problems will emerge, and constitutional text may well fail to solve them, or even to address them.*13* Thus, advances in genetic research, anthropology, primatology, ethology, and psychology may challenge judges to recognize a new reality through a case resembling Evelyn Hart’s in the near future. In the following Brief, we argue the moral imperative for this legal development, and we show how a plaintiff like Evelyn Hart can be accommodated within existing Constitutional provisions.

Toshisada Nishida, a Professor of Zoology, has compared the other hominids, with their complex cultures and cognitive abilities, to members of hunter-gatherer societies.*14* Were our government to import humans from such a society in order to subject them to lifelong confinement and use them in painful research for the benefit of U.S. citizens, the idea would be universally denounced as unconscionable, and our Constitution would be invoked to confirm what our moral senses tell us. In light of our knowledge about other great apes, their importation and enslavement ought to provoke the same responses.

The dual task of this Brief is to (i) demonstrate what we now know about certain non-human great apes, in the light of scientific evidence, which will itself establish the nature of the moral imperative, and (ii) to show how this new knowledge entitles Evelyn Hart, and others similarly situated, to the protection afforded “persons” under the Fifth, Eighth, Thirteenth, and Fourteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution.

EVELYN HART, by her Guardian Ad Litem, Robin Lane, Petitioners vs. DONNA E. DOE, SECRETARY, DEPARTMENT OF HEALTH AND HUMAN SERVICES, Respondent.

No. 14-111.

United States Supreme Court Petitioner’s Brief. October Term, 2006. 8 December 2006. Writ Of Certiorari to the United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit

BRIEF FOR PETITIONER

Lee Hall and Anthony Jon Waters, Attorneys for Petitioner Guardian Ad Litem

QUESTION PRESENTED FOR REVIEW

Is a non-human great ape a person for purposes of Due Process and Equal Protection components of the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments of the United States Constitution? Do the Eighth and Thirteenth Amendments to the United States Constitution, as well as U.S. obligations under international law, additionally protect the non-human great ape’s interest in freedom and bodily integrity?

CONSTITUTIONAL PROVISIONS INVOLVED

The Fifth Amendment to the Constitution of the United States provides in pertinent part: No person shall…be deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law. The Eighth Amendment to the Constitution of the United States provides in pertinent part: [C]ruel and unusual punishment [shall not be] inflicted. The Thirteenth Amendment to the Constitution of the United States provides in pertinent part: Neither slavery not involuntary servitude, except as a punishment for a crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted, shall exist within the United States, or any place subject to their jurisdiction. The Fourteenth Amendment to the Constitution of the United States provides in pertinent part: No State shall… deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.

STATEMENT OF THE CASE

This case raises the important issue of inclusion within the class of persons whose rights are constitutionally protected. Petitioner asserts that the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia incorrectly determined that she is not a person for the purpose of the Constitution; and the consequent denial of protection to Petitioner’s fundamental interests is therefore unconstitutional. The United States Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia declined to address this issue, invoking third-party standing barriers read into Article III of the Constitution in Sierra Club v. Morton*15* and Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife.*16* Petitioner, however, brings her claim in her own name. Based on the clear and present evidence of her eligibility, Evelyn Hart appears today to assert her right to be removed from the legal category of “property” and included within the category of “person” in so far as the category to which she is assigned affects the protection of her fundamental interests in life and in freedom from captivity and torture.

PARTIES TO THE PROCEEDINGS

PETITIONER: Evelyn Hart, also known as CH-594, through her Guardian Ad Litem, Robin Lane RESPONDENT: Donna E. Doe, Secretary, U.S. Department of Health and Human Services

STATEMENT OF JURISDICTION

The jurisdiction of the Court is invoked under 28 U.S.C. §1254(1) and under the general federal question provision, 28 U.S.C. § 1331. The appeal was filed on 2 February 2006 from a Memorandum Opinion and Order, entered by the Court of Appeals on 1 January 2006, dismissing the case.

PROCEEDINGS BELOW

A. Proceedings

Before the District Court Robin Lane appeared before this Court as guardian ad litem on behalf of Petitioner. Evelyn Hart thus filed suit in U.S. District Court challenging the validity of the National Institutes of Health (NIH) documents that register her as property and authorize her removal to the Yerkes Regional Primate Research Center at Emory University for use as a subject in “invasive biomedical research.”*17* Petitioner asserts the act of registering herself as property under NIH regulations violates the Due Process component of the Fifth Amendment, the equal protection component of the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause, the Eighth Amendment prohibiting cruel and unusual punishment, and the Thirteenth Amendment barring slavery. Respondents requested dismissal of the case for failure to state a claim; Respondents further stated that Evelyn Hart did not exist and identified the Petitioner as CH-594.

In a Memorandum Opinion and Order filed April 29, 2013, the case was dismissed by Judge Sue A. Sponte, United States District Judge for the District of Columbia, on the basis that Evelyn Hart lacked standing to challenge the NIH records defining her as NIH property, and that Evelyn Hart was legally under the ownership and control of the NIH and called CH-594.

B. Proceedings Before The Court of Appeals

The Petitioner appealed to the Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia Circuit. The Court of Appeals held that Professor Lane, in his own right, lacked standing to bring this action; and in light of controlling precedent, NIH owns the chimpanzee, who has no cause of action of her own. In addition to citing the stringent requirements for third-party standing,*18* the Court of Appeals cited Int’l Primate Prot. League v. Adm’rs of the Tulane Educ’l Fund*19* in support of the dismissal of Evelyn Hart’s case. Specifically, because NIH research is overseen by Institutional Animal Care and Use Committees (IACUCs), the public interest in subjects’ welfare is represented; thus Evelyn Hart’s claims fall outside of the Animal Welfare Act “zones of interest.”*20*

Moreover, the Court held that no non-human member of the great ape species may present “cases” or “controversies” under Article III of the Constitution.*21* Judge Wilde dissented. She concluded:

The cases cited by the majority are not appropriate precedent to the case of Evelyn Hart, given modern scientific knowledge about great apes. Here we are asked to consider a plaintiff who can reason and communicate at the level of a young child. The majority fails to find standing for a laboratory tool, but Evelyn Hart defies such categorization. The court would find standing in cases of experimentation upon intellectually incapacitated humans; of that, there is no doubt.

Evelyn Hart has a greater capacity to reason and to suffer than some humans, whom we rightly protect, and we pay homage to an arbitrary distinction if we refuse to consider her capacity to suffer simply because she does not look like us. In light of current knowledge about the social and psychological needs and capacities of the great ape species as demonstrated by evidence submitted, Evelyn Hart presents a compelling case, deserving of review.

This Court thereafter granted certiorari.

STATEMENT OF FACTS

Petitioner Evelyn Hart is a seven-year-old chimpanzee. Hart is also identified by the number CH-594, used in place of her name to preclude any tendency on the part of doctors, researchers, and laboratory technicians to become emotionally involved with her,*22* a technique also used for prisoners and inmates of concentration camps. It is not known whether Evelyn Hart, along with twenty-six of her lab mates, would survive the onset of full-blown symptoms of the planned laboratory-induced illness.

Evelyn Hart is currently in good health, with the exception of some evident damage to the tissue of her right leg, reportedly caused by an accident during training to ride a motorbike in a night club act, before her second birthday. At the age of three, she was spotted by an unmarried septuagenarian, Hildegarde Hart, who was a well-known nightclub singer in the 1950s. Ms. Hart adopted the chimpanzee, named her Evelyn, and treated her much as she would have treated her own human child. Evelyn became known in the social circle at events hosted by Ms. Hart, where the chimpanzee would pass hors d’oeuvre and play games with the guests.

On 15 March 2013, Ms. Hart passed away. Her will named Evelyn and a local Christian Scientist church as legatees to the house, an extensive art collection, and stocks valued at $840,000. Dr. Laughlin Ayre, a second cousin whom Ms. Hart had not seen for more than fifteen years, successfully contested her will as a product of an insane delusion. Dr. Ayre removed the art collection from the Hart home, and proceeded to list the home for sale. Although he clearly knew of Evelyn’s existence, Dr. Ayre apparently ignored her presence in the house at that time.

Robin Lane is a lecturer in psychology and a Christian Scientist practitioner. In April, Professor Lane met Dr. Ayre on the Hart property, as Ayre was removing the furniture from the Hart home. Lane explained that he had come to find Evelyn, and that, in spite of Ayre’s prevailing suit in orphan’s court, Lane was willing to look after Evelyn even without a precatory inheritance. Ayre had Lane barred from the property.

The Humane Society of Eden Falls, Maryland was called to the late Ms. Hart’s home on 26 June 2013 by a neighbour who noticed Evelyn attempting to open a first-floor window. Tracy Quinn, one of the animal control officers who responded to the call, found Evelyn in the late Ms. Hart’s bedroom, rocking, and later diagnosed as suffering from early stages of malnutrition and dehydration. A veterinarian was called to the shelter where Evelyn had been taken; he administered a subcutaneous saline solution to Evelyn. The officers contacted Dr. Ayre after looking into the property records. According to their reports, Dr. Ayre was gruff initially; but he grew increasingly attentive and, by the end of the telephone conversation, promised to drive to the shelter immediately. He arrived, carrying a case of wine for the shelter employees and a fruit basket for Evelyn. He demanded that Evelyn be surrendered to him, showing as proof of ownership a document issued by the probate court.

Two days later, Dr. Ayre walked into the National Institutes of Health in Rockville, Maryland, holding Evelyn’s hand. When he walked back out, he held only a receipt. Evelyn Hart is slated for use in invasive biomedical research as part of an ongoing project funded by the National Institutes of Health (“NIH”). She is to be shipped to Emory University, in Atlanta, U.S., and placed in a viral disease study currently in progress.

Evelyn Hart’s case was dismissed by the Court of Appeals, where she was deemed to be property. She appeals to the United States Supreme Court, challenging precisely such classification through this claim.

SUMMARY OF ARGUMENT

Plaintiff Evelyn Hart is a member of a class known as the non-human great apes—a category that includes chimpanzees, gorillas, bonobos and orang-utans. The core problem she faces is that the law, as it now stands, distinguishes between the “personhood” of human beings and the property status—that is, the denial of personhood—to non-human great apes. The Supreme Court should change that by recognizing that, with respect to the essential purposes of the Fifth, Eighth, Thirteenth, and Fourteenth Amendments, Evelyn Hart is a person. Her confinement, torture, and death must be prohibited because there is no moral quality which separates her from other people who are rightly protected under the Constitution.

In common with many mentally disabled people, Hart has capacities which differ from those of most human adults. But even when mentally disabled humans function only on a basic level, they are “persons” in the eyes of the law. Therefore, the government’s interest in performing highly dangerous and painful research on Evelyn Hart must be subjected to the most stringent level of scrutiny.

Regulations would differentiate between human and non-human apes. There are various ways to apply the Bill of Rights. The Supreme Court has held, however, that where certain fundamental rights are involved, regulation limiting these rights may be justified only by a compelling state interest. The legislative enactments must be narrowly drawn to express only the legitimate interests at stake.*23* Unjustified deprivation of liberty, the infliction of severe pain, and the killing of any individual great ape, human or non-human, violates fundamental rights.

Being a legal person, Evelyn Hart has a fundamental interest in life and liberty. The Fifth Amendment Due Process Clause, as well as the Equal Protection and Due Process provisions of the Fourteenth Amendment, expressly protect “any person.”*24* Moreover, a denial of legal protection would violate the Thirteenth Amendment’s prohibition of “involuntary servitude, except as punishment for a crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted.”*25* Petitioner notes that she has committed no crime and has never been convicted of any; therefore her involuntary servitude to the state university or to the National Institutes of Health is unconstitutional.

Finally, Petitioner argues that because she is a legal person, the plans of the National Institutes of Health and Emory University offend the Eighth Amendment to the United States Constitution, as well as the prohibition of torture, a basic principle of customary international law referenced by implication in the United States Constitution in article. 1, § 8, clause 10.

Petitioner presents a justifiable controversy and has a stake in its outcome. The “logical nexus between the status asserted and the claim sought to be adjudicated”*26* and the “necessary degree of contentiousness”*27* are both present. In short, the answer to the question “is there an injured person speaking?” is yes.*28* Because of the serious impact the outcome of this case will have on her life, and because of the importance of the issues presented by this pressing legal question, Evelyn Hart asks this Court to review the merits of her plea, and to grant her freedom.

ARGUMENT I. NON-HUMAN GREAT APES ARE PERSONS FOR THE PURPOSE OF THE CORE PROTECTIONS OF DUE PROCESS AND EQUAL PROTECTION

A. LEGAL RECOGNITION OF CANDIDATES FOR INCLUSION AS PERSONS HAS ALWAYS DEVELOPED IN ACCORDANCE WITH HUMAN KNOWLEDGE AND THE MORES OF THE TIME

The Constitution includes no definition of a person.*29* Therein lies much of the dynamism of our constitutional jurisprudence. Professor Tribe explains this eloquently when he notes that “[a]ny fundamental rights of personhood and privacy too precisely or inflexibly defined defy the seasons and are likely to be bypassed by the spring floods.”*30* By any meaningful set of criteria, modern knowledge demonstrates that non-human great apes are persons, morally and legally entitled to certain basic rights under the Constitution.

Non-human hominids might have a less complex set of values than humans have.*31* But legal equality does not mean equivalence: it does not mean that all individuals are the same, or have the same needs. Petitioner makes no demand for permission to vote or to hold public office, but for freedom from dire physical and emotional pain. Although Petitioner does not need each and every right that is secured for humans by means of constitutional protections, her demonstrated capacities belie any claim that she merits no basic rights. Classifying her as property—like a building or a desk—ought to shock the conscience, because it condemns her to a life of severe distress.

Because Hart satisfies the most fundamental criteria of personhood, she must be classified accordingly: as a person who merits an appropriately limited set of constitutional rights. We now know that the members of the great ape family—the chimpanzee, the bonobo, the gorilla, the orang-utan, and the human—are all rational beings with complex emotional lives and strong social bonds that last a lifetime.*32* All can be harmed, and they are aware that they are being harmed.*33* The fact that the framers of the Constitution did not know these facts does not render our modern understanding unfaithful to their essential objectives.

Western science has only recently begun to learn about the social structure of non-human great apes. Not until the 1960s did we know that tools are an integral part of their lives in nature.*34* It would have been impossible to anticipate such discoveries two centuries earlier. Nevertheless, the Constitution is able to adapt to the knowledge and social realities of its time.*35*

Petitioner does not deny the importance of stability in the interpretation of individual rights; but “[t]he crucial stability in any case is that of integrity: the system of rights must be interpreted, so far as possible, as expressing a coherent vision of justice.”*36* This legal evolution attests to one of the distinguishing features of the Constitution: its flexibility.*37*

The framers of the Fourteenth Amendment did not presume that “equal protection of the laws” meant a society free from segregated schooling.*38* Yet in 1954, eighty-six years after the ratification of the Fourteenth Amendment, the Court did in fact decide that segregated schools could not continue to co-exist with the Amendment.*39* Scientific knowledge, and the view of our society and our universe it creates, evolves over the centuries.*40* Knowing, then, that the public’s morality and sense of purpose do change, we turn now to the philosophical elements of personhood.

B. NON-HUMAN GREAT APES MEET THE PHILOSOPHICAL CRITERIA FOR PERSONHOOD

Philosophers, ancient and modern, agree on the basic components of personhood. The word “person” was introduced into philosophical discourse by the Stoic philosopher Epictetus, who used it to describe the role one played in life.*41* Theologian Joseph Fletcher provided a list of “indicators of humanhood” that includes self-awareness, self-control, a sense of the future, a sense of the past, the capacity to relate to others, concern for others, curiosity, and communication.*42* Bioethicist Peter Singer speaks of the same qualities, but notes that they do not define the biological species Homo sapiens so much as they describe elements of personhood.*43*

John Locke defined a person as a “thinking intelligent being that has reason and reflection and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places.”*44* Locke’s definition makes “person” close to Fletcher’s “human” except that it selects thinking and self-awareness as the central characteristics.*45*

The attributes of personhood most frequently mentioned and accepted are clearly present in all of the non-human great apes.*46* Being a member of the class of non-human great apes, Petitioner Hart meets the relevant philosophical criteria of personhood in a similar manner to the way humans meet those same criteria. Thus her exclusion from our moral consideration is irrational and arbitrary—not only morally unjustifiable.*47* This becomes clear when we consider and apply the indicators of “personhood” recognized by Locke and, more recently, by Singer.

1. Rationality and self-awareness.

Dr. Goodall’s thirty-eight years of observing chimpanzees at the Gombe Stream Reserve in Tanzania have been described as a longitudinal study of another culture.*48* Goodall’s writings include the best-known descriptions of non-human tool-making and tool-using in natural environments; these skills were previously considered unique to humans.*49* Non-human hominids’ comprehension of the causality of fashioning and employing tools reflects the capacity for complex problem-solving abilities. *50* Pressures associated with complex social living require cognitive characteristics that have been observed in the social interactions of other great ape species.*51* Among these are the ability, also once thought uniquely human, to appreciate the perspective of another individual.*52*

With respect to what Locke terms “reflection,” we might ask whether a non-human hominid recognizes an experience as her own experience, and whether she is able to think about an experience without prompting from external stimuli. Self-consciousness encompasses an awareness of oneself and others;*53* as we shall see below, non-human great apes demonstrate this quality at a sophisticated level, displaying their understanding that others also have mental states and thoughts.*54* Before one can conceive of another’s perspective, one must understand one’s own self-image.*55*

In 1970, G.G. Gallup, Jr. first demonstrated that chimpanzees could recognize themselves in a mirror after being marked with vibrant red dye while asleep; they later used the mirror to investigate areas of their bodies which they could not otherwise see.*56* Passing the mirror self-recognition test continues to be most widely accepted as evidence for self-recognition and, in turn, some facet of self-awareness.*57*

2. Self-control.

Tetsuro Matsuzawa and his team at Kyoto University in Japan studied food retrieval by pairs of chimpanzees—a “witness” who had seen food being hidden and a “bystander” who hadn’t.*58* The “bystander” chimpanzee tended to follow the “witness,” apparently understanding the witness’s knowledge.*59* Self-control was exhibited by the witness, who would occasionally deceive the other by avoiding the food and leading the bystander to an empty box.*60*

3. A sense of the future.

Frans de Waal has discussed Kakowet, a bonobo who spotted zoo keepers turning on water valves that threatened to flood a nearby moat where infant apes were playing.*61* Kakowet warned a zoo keeper and helped rescue the babies.*62* This demonstration of the bonobo’s ability to know that babies would be in the path of rushing water and unable to save themselves is an example of advanced thinking which, like the abilities to make and to use tools, was once considered uniquely human.*63*

4. A sense of the past.

Gloria Grow runs the Fauna Foundation, a sanctuary for fifteen chimpanzees who were released from a New York laboratory that closed in 1997.*64* She has written a number of accounts evidencing chimpanzees’ memory of the past.*65* Among many such events recorded by Grow, a few stand out as particularly disturbing. An example is an incident which took place when Grow received a shipment of wood pellets for the gas stove, got a trolley from behind the sanctuary building, loaded the bags of pellets on to the trolley, and pulled it past the chimpanzees to the stove.*66* As she did so, chimpanzees Tom and Pablo simultaneously emitted a piercing shriek, whereupon all fifteen of the chimpanzees lunged to the front where Grow was pulling the trolley.*67* Within seconds, all fifteen were clinging to the bars, rocking back and forth, screaming aggressively and staring angrily at Gloria.*68* Then Gloria remembered: this was the trolley that came from the laboratory, and this was the first time the chimpanzees had seen it in two years.*69* That trolley had been used in the lab to transport unconscious chimpanzees from their cages to the surgery room.*70*

This capacity to recall traumatic events indicates not only the depth of the psychic pain the great apes can experience, but also the intensity of fear they can feel in anticipation of continued and future suffering.*71* Thus when non-human great apes are held for biomedical research, they are forced to endure not only the physical pain, but also the memory of past injuries, together with the reality that they are trapped and helpless to avoid the imposition of future pain.*72*

5. Capacity to relate to others.

Sarah, an adult female chimpanzee, was presented a series of videotaped sequences depicting a human experiencing some type of problem.*73* One scene showed a human being shivering violently while standing next to a disconnected portable heater.*74* As Sarah watched, the video was interrupted just when the actor would have likely thought of a solution.*75* Sarah was then required to choose the best of several photographs showing a viable solution.*76* Sarah selected a picture of a connected heater. Of eight problems shown to her on videotape, Sarah correctly answered seven problems.*77* Thus Sarah demonstrated the ability of non-human great apes to interpret a situation from another’s point of view.

Another example of non-human hominids’ capacity to relate to others is described by Roger Fouts, a psychology professor at Central Washington University, and Co-director of the Chimpanzee and Human Communication Institute.*78* He recounts an interaction between Washoe, an adult chimpanzee, and a volunteer who worked every day with her.*79* When the volunteer became pregnant, Washoe, who had had two pregnancies of her own (both ending in early death), was very attentive and would ask the volunteer, through sign language, about the baby.*80* At one point, the volunteer stopped coming to see Washoe.*81* When she returned, Washoe acknowledged the volunteer but kept her distance, as if hurt by the volunteer’s absence.*82* The volunteer explained to Washoe that she had miscarried, signing, “My baby died.” Washoe looked at the volunteer, and signed, “Cry.” Later, as the volunteer was leaving, Washoe signed, “Please person hug.”*83*

6. Concern for others.

From John Locke’s perspective, concern for others is irrelevant to the question of Hart’s personhood; it is, however, relevant to establishing, in a fuller sense, the arbitrariness of denying basic legal protections to some hominids, but not all.*84* The concern that non-human hominids are able to extend to others is illustrated by the U.S. publication People Magazine, which features articles about people whose situations appeal to the general interest. Among the “twenty-five most intriguing people” of 1996, the magazine listed a gorilla named Binti Jua.*85*

Binti was decorated with a medal from the American Legion, and presented with an honorary membership in a Downey, California Parent-Teacher Association, after she rescued a three-year-old child who fell twenty-four feet to the cement floor of the gorilla enclosure at Brookfield Zoo in Illinois.*86* In a widely televised scene, Binti, with her own infant on her back, lifted the unconscious human child, carried him across the compound and, rocking him softly, laid him before the entrance where the paramedics and zoo staff were waiting.*87* The child recovered.*88*

We may ask whether Binti could comprehend the moral significance of her act. Philosophers have argued the same question, but in the context of human acts of altruism.*89* Yet, as Sapontzis so eloquently puts it, if we ascribed moral actions only to those who could answer the questions of moral theory, “there would be very few moral actions.”*90*

Roger Fouts commented thus on Binti’s act: “Binti clearly demonstrates that, just as some humans are capable of compassion, caring, and altruistic acts, so too are some members of the gorilla species…Obviously compassionate empathy is an adaptive trait. If it were not, very few infants of any species with long childhoods that depend on their mother’s compassionate empathy would survive.”*91* This story affords substantial evidence that moral responsibility is not the exclusive domain of human beings and that concern for others is felt, and acted upon, by persons like Binti Jua.

7. Curiosity.

Roger Fouts describes in detail a rather entertaining demonstration of chimpanzee Washoe’s curiosity—and of her ability to contrive an experiment to satisfy that curiosity. Fouts purchased a doormat for Washoe.*92* He waited for her to inspect it carefully, as she did with all new objects.*93*But she took one look at the mat and jumped back, and crouched in a corner.*94* Suddenly she stood up, grabbed one of her dolls, approached the mat within the distance of her own height, and tossed the doll on top of the mat.*95* She watched intently for several minutes, but nothing happened to the doll.*96* Then, Washoe approached the mat, snatched the doll, and carefully inspected it. After that, Washoe began using the doormat with no evident fear.*97*

8. Communication.

Although not a criterion for Lockean personhood, the ability to communicate underscores the richness of all great apes’ social lives.*98*

Sue Savage-Rumbaugh, Professor of Biology and Psychology at the Georgia State University, has studied cognition in humans and non-human apes since 1972.*99* In her study, and in others,*100* gorillas, orang-utans, bonobos, and chimpanzees have proved capable of grasping various components of human language in the forms of signs, symbol, and spoken English.*101* They use sign language to converse with humans, with each other, and to themselves.*102*They laugh at their own jokes and those of others.*103*

Francine Patterson was awarded a doctorate in developmental psychology for her studies of several gorillas who are able to communicate in human language.*104* One of these gorillas, Koko, has acquired a vocabulary in sign language exceeding 1,000 words and replies to both signed and spoken questions.*105* Koko, who has achieved scores between 85 and 95 on the Stanford-Binet Intelligence Test,*106* differentiates between words used in a concrete sense and in the abstract. For example, when asked to define “hard,” she has answered with “work” as well as “rock.”*107* She shortens words and creates puns (for example, using the sign for “knock” as a substitute for the word “obnoxious” based on the auditory similarity in the spoken versions of the two words.)*108* She invents terms when no appropriate name is available (for example, “bottle necklace” for a six-pack soda can holder.)*109* Koko makes faces and examines herself in a mirror; she enjoys imaginary play, alone and with others.*110* She has been known to scream when angered, and to cry when left alone.*111* She anticipates others’ reactions to her acts, and sometimes lies to avoid disapproval.*112* She becomes visibly uneasy when asked to discuss death—her own, or that of others.*113* Her reaction to the idea of facing death in her future matches, at a sophisticated level, Locke’s view of one’s ability to perceive oneself as oneself, “in different times and places,” as necessary for personhood.

Describing the chimpanzee’s emotional complexity, Goodall observes, “a young chimpanzee who loses his or her mother will show signs very similar to clinical depression in humans, signs which we describe as grief.”*114* Dr. Goodall has informed scientists, many of whom inject diseases into great apes, test drugs on them, and dissect them, that the apes are not only like us physiologically, which they find useful, but also psychologically.*115*

C. CONTINUED CLASSIFICATION OF NON-HUMAN GREAT APES AS MERE PROPERTY IS BOTH MORALLY AND LEGALLY INTOLERABLE

The capacities of non-human great apes correspond with the core elements of personhood. This fact renders their continued classification as property intolerable. In recognition of the special burden a court faces when asked to apply existing law to a new type of plaintiff, Petitioner has provided the underpinnings—philosophical, historical, and legal—for her identity before the court.

For persons do not appear before a court self-defined or ready-made. A court must make a judgment before it can perceive, hear, or talk about “she,” “you,” “the plaintiff,” or whatever other term is used to address one who argues the merits of her case.*116*

In books and in common speech, “person” is often used as meaning a human being, but the legal meaning of a “person” is one who has legal rights and duties.*117* Whether an entity ought to be considered a legal person depends on whether the entity can and should be afforded a set of legal rights and duties.*118*

The particular bundle of rights and duties that accompanies legal personhood already varies according to the nature of the entity. For example, corporations are legal persons, but they have different sets of legal rights and duties from natural persons.*119* Plaintiff Hart urges this Court to deal with her on the basis of her capacities—that is, what her intellectual and emotional life is like. Hart asks this Court to put aside any prejudices which are based on the fact that she is not a member of our species, or that she looks different from other plaintiffs.

The law recognizes all human beings as having some basic rights and interests that must be protected. Hart shares morally relevant traits with humans, which underscores the need to respect her rights and interests. In addressing the objection that rights should not be given without duties, it is essential to remember that the intellectually disabled have rights, although we would not hold them responsible for their actions in all cases.*120* The situation is quite the same here. Hart is a sentient, self-aware being. In human terms, she may not be at the level at which we would attribute responsibility to her, as we would to a mature human, but that is no reason for denying her basic rights. This is consistent with the fundamental legal premise that the particular bundle of rights and duties that accompanies legal personhood varies according to the nature of the entity.

Professor Singer explains that admitting non-human great apes into a community of equals can be urged without asserting “equivalence”:*121* When people first hear the term “the community of equals”, they sometimes think “equal” means “the same”, or that members of the “community of equals” should be treated in exactly the same way. This is not true for humans, nor is it true for the other great apes. For instance, considering human physiology and the strength of human arms, it would be absurd to insist that all humans should have an opportunity to live in trees. For orang-utans, however, with their greater strength and agility when off the ground, and their preference for living in trees, such a demand makes considerable sense. When we include our fellow apes in the community of equals, we assert that they are our moral equals in the crucial areas of right to life, protection of freedom, and prohibition of torture.*122*

II. RELIEF IS NECESSARY TO PROTECT PETITIONER’S RIGHTS UNDER THE FIFTH AND FOURTEENTH AMENDMENTS

A. INFRINGEMENT ON PETITIONER’S LIFE, LIBERTY, AND BODILY INTEGRITY OFFENDS THE DUE PROCESS CLAUSE IN THE FIFTH AND FOURTEENTH AMENDMENTS

In 1982, the Supreme Court considered for the first time the substantive due process rights of the involuntarily-committed mentally disabled, and held that the Constitution protected Nicholas Romeo, a profoundly mentally disabled man, from bodily injury and bodily restraints at the institution.*123* Thus the majority duly found constitutional protection under the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause for a person who, although 33 years old, had the mental capacity of an 18-month-old child, with an I.Q. between 8 and 10, unable to talk and lacking in the most basic self-care skills.*124* The Court stated that in the past, courts have noted that “the right to personal security constitutes an ‘historic liberty interest’ protected substantively by the Due Process Clause.”*125*

The social skills that guide our lives, a measure of our ability to think our way into the minds of other individuals, does not appear until about the age of three or four in normal human children.*126* Many autistic humans never develop to that stage.*127* Non-human great apes exceed the capabilities of autistic humans individuals in those key social skills.*128*

Jane Goodall has analyzed how chimpanzees communicate feelings such as fear, stress, anger, and pleasure.*129* She includes visual, tactile, auditory, the use of symbols, and other forms of communication, posture, and smell.*130* There is a documented overlap between these forms of communication and those observed in the severely mentally disabled.*131* In fact, apes’ ability to communicate in sign language by initiating conversation and inventing new words demonstrates that there is much that a chimpanzee or a gorilla can do that a profoundly mentally disabled human cannot do.*132*

The fact that Evelyn Hart has greater and more fully developed cognitive capacities than Nicholas Romeo makes plain that a mechanical denial of all Constitutional protections to her is no longer legally or morally tolerable. In the instant case, the purpose of the proposed involuntary confinement of Evelyn Hart at Emory University is to subject her to non-therapeutic invasive research, a severe burden on her most fundamental interests. The imposition of this burden is not for her own protection: she stands to gain no benefit from it.

Moreover, Petitioner would suffer greatly from laboratory confinement itself.*133* Thus, the effect of the protection given by due process, and the importance of her liberty, have as much validity to Evelyn Hart as to most human beings.

Petitioner does not ask this Court to unearth any new fundamental rights which might be embedded in the Due Process Clause. That clause expressly protects life and liberty, the core interests claimed by Petitioner.*134* Indeed, the protection of individual interests in life and liberty is one of the defining characteristics of our constitutional system. The tradition of flexible interpretation of a living constitution permits the courts to adjust the scope of these fundamental protections to the needs of the times.*135*

Petitioner appreciates that no constitutional right, not even liberty, is absolute. But absent an extremely compelling interest, fundamental rights cannot be violated.*136* What type of state interest would permit human confinement, mutilation, and so forth? The interest would have to be extraordinary; otherwise the violations of basic rights involved would be unconscionable, as it is in situations described in later sections of this Brief.

If this Court were to deny Evelyn Hart’s standing, it would call into question the foundation of certain recently acknowledged rights of the mentally disabled. Petitioner asserts that the Due Process Clause protects her life and future; and that because she has the psychological capacity to appreciate both liberty and the deprivation of liberty, she is entitled to be classified as a person for purposes of Due Process under the Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments.

B. FORCING THE PETITIONER TO SUBMIT TO INVASIVE RESEARCH WOULD VIOLATE CONSTITUTIONAL GUARANTEES OF EQUAL PROTECTION OF THE FEDERAL AND STATE LAWS

1. Petitioner’s mental and physical suffering would be comparable to the suffering of a human subjected to invasive scientific research; a failure to protect her would be a violation of the guarantee of equal protection of fundamental rights.

The test of constitutional validity traditionally applied in the area of social and economic legislation is whether or not a law has a rational relation to a valid state objective.*137* The present case involves a most fundamental aspect of liberty: the plan to restrain her and to force her to submit to harmful physical intrusions. Petitioner therefore asks this Court to exercise the heightened scrutiny reserved for those instances where the Court reviews practices affecting fundamental rights.*138*

Petitioner further asserts that characteristics attributed to her and to other non-human great apes necessarily implicate equal protection concerns.*139*Evelyn Hart is a member of the group Hominoidea, the taxonomical group to which human beings also belong.*140* Being a non-human great ape means she can be bought and sold, treated as an object of commerce, and exploited for profit.*141* Others invoke her non-human status to justify future confinement and involuntary submission to what can only be called torture, with the real possibility of death resulting.*142* Hart argues that each of these three predicaments interferes with, and has an intolerable impact on, her most fundamental needs and interests.

A prejudice essentially involves a failure to treat a group appropriately, based on arbitrary or irrelevant grounds.*143* Although Evelyn Hart and those in her class possess characteristics and needs that are relevant to decisions about how she should be treated, this factor is not controlling where the most fundamental rights of life and liberty are concerned. In light of the competitive aspects of medical research,*144* the systematic abuse of non-human great apes is unlikely to be eliminated voluntarily by those in the field.*145* Because legislative action to rectify her situation is extremely unlikely, Petitioner Hart urges this Court to outlaw such discrimination.*146*

As one member of this present Court once said: “through ignorance and prejudice, [they] have been subjected to a history of unfair and often grotesque mistreatment.”*147* Justice Stevens was referring to the plight of mentally disabled humans, but he could as well have been describing the grotesque mistreatment of the other great apes, by humans. Human knowledge about the sensitivities of the other great apes is, admittedly, a recent phenomenon, but it is precisely because we are no longer ignorant about those sensitivities that nothing can justify the continuing, grotesque mistreatment of chimpanzees and other great apes.

2. The Subjection of Petitioner to Sale and Subsequent Invasive Research Violates the Equal Protection Component of the Fifth Amendment

The protections invoked in the previous section apply with equal force against the federal government. In Petitioner’s case, the National Institutes of Health decision to dispose of her as an item of property violates the equal protection component of The Fifth Amendment’s Due Process clause. Although the Fifth Amendment (which is applicable to the federal government and the District of Columbia)*148* does not contain an equal protection clause like that found in the Fourteenth Amendment (which applies only to the states),*149* this Court has recognized that “discrimination may be so unjustifiable as to be violative of due process.”*150* The “equal protection of the laws” is a more explicit safeguard against prohibited unfairness than “due process of law,” and consequently, the latter can encompass the former.

Thus: Particular constitutional rights that follow from the best interpretation of the equal protection clause, for example, will very likely also follow from the best interpretation of the due process clause. The Supreme Court had no difficulty in deciding that although the equal protection clause does not apply to the District of Columbia, racial segregation in the District’s schools is nevertheless unconstitutional under the due process clause, which does apply to it. *151*

3. The Subjection of Petitioner to Invasive Research at the State University is Not Narrowly Tailored to the State Interest Invoked, and Violates the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment

The Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment commands that no state shall “deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws,”*152* and mandates the states to treat all persons similarly situated, alike.*153* In determining which classifications may be unconstitutionally discriminatory, this Court has never been wedded to fixed concepts of equality.*154* “[H]istory makes it clear that constitutional principles of equality, like those of liberty, property, and due process, evolve over time….”*155*

The right to life is implicitly protected by the Constitution.*156* The liberty interest in bodily integrity and physical freedom is also fundamental.*157* Where legislation affects these rights, the government must show a compelling interest at stake; a “narrowly tailored” connection between the challenged governmental action and the governmental interest;*158* and that the government could not secure its compelling interest by a different classification or by less drastic means.*159*

In 1996, the National Institutes of Health (“NIH”) announced a decision to “redirect some of the $10 million that the National Center for Research Resources now spends on chimpanzee based research.”*160* The NIH cited time expenditures and failure to find applicable results. Thus, the State’s interest in general research using non-human hominids is not, in fact, narrowly tailored and is not claimed to be an immediate or unique method for curing disease. Alternative methodologies to effectively promote the public interest can and should be made available. But even if they were not, Petitioner insists that the government must still demonstrate a compelling interest in continued discrimination against Petitioner and all members of her class. This is because whenever an illegitimate intrusion is alleged, “[t]he inquiry must examine likely results. It must seek out submerged classifications or differential impacts.

In an epidemic the state assuredly has the power to require testing, vaccination, and quarantine, but those intrusions must be measured for their necessity and efficacy, and if the intrusions are extreme alternatives must be considered.”*161* In the present case, we must consider the purpose asserted by the National Institutes of Health: that is, the goal of public health. Petitioner acknowledges the legitimacy and the importance of this objective, but argues that the government has failed to establish a compelling or immediate need for biomedical experiments involving non-human great apes to achieve that stated objective. Petitioner’s particular and fundamental interests outweigh whatever generalized interest the state may have in the goal of attaining knowledge about human disease. As the reason for carrying out the experiment becomesless about individual therapy, and more about a quest for general knowledge, the value of the government interest in protecting the research is correspondingly diminished.*162*

Obviously, neither Evelyn Hart nor her class is in any way helped by the research in issue. Accordingly, we urge that the permission for this research be declared an invalid infringement of the plaintiff’s Due Process and Equal Protection rights.

C. SAFEGUARDING THE RIGHTS OF PERSONS SUBJECTED TO SCIENTIFIC EXPERIMENTATION IS A CRITICAL COUNTERVAILING CONCERN TO THE STATE

The government contends that the possible benefits to society resulting from medical experimentation are the only state interest raised in Hart’s case. Petitioner asserts, on the contrary, that safeguarding the rights of individuals in the conduct of research projects is a momentous countervailing concern to the state. The asserted interest in health implicates much more than just anatomy and pharmacology; it involves helping people instead of harming them. In a country that spends many billions of dollars each year on the consequences of societal violence,*163* the state interest in public health and safety is more effectively served by promoting respect for life.

As applied to the lives of non-human great apes, recognition of this principle would reflect the increased understanding of them that science has gained over the past thirty years. Field studies, laboratory work, and language-acquisition research demonstrate that human and non-human great apes are very similar, and could benefit from legal protections for similar reasons. Thus, although both human and non-human great apes provide effective models in some studies, this fact does not justify their use.*164* The best research tool for the study of human diseases is a human being, but it has generally not been argued, for example, that the great benefits of experimenting on human beings with IQs below a certain number would justify an abrogation of their status of persons. For example, not even anencephalics—human babies born with a only a brain stem and with no chance of ever becoming conscious—may be used as the subjects of lethal experimentation, or for organ donations to save other babies’ lives.*165*

Frederick Coulston resorted to testing on chimpanzees “when his work with human subjects—prisoners—was halted in the 1960s.”*166* Roger Fouts has commented: “‘Eventually we realized it was wrong to experiment on prisoners, and our closest relatives, the chimpanzees, are the next step’…‘People say, “You’d want to use a chimp’s organs if it would save your child.” Well, I’d want to use my neighbor’s organs if it would save my child, but that doesn’t mean I should.’”*167*

Hippocrates warned physicians: “As to diseases, make a habit of two things—to help, or at least to do no harm.”*168* In Hippocrates’s day, physicians carried out experiments, but they did so primarily to help individuals who did not respond to customary remedies.*169* In modern medical science, experimentation is widespread, not for individual therapy, but in the hope of advancing scientific knowledge.*170*

In any constitutional analysis of each experiment, individual liberty interests must be balanced against the relevant state interests.*171* Therapeutic experimentation, which attempts to address a concrete health problem, implicates a stronger state interest than does research done in the hope, or even the expectation, of acquiring generalized scientific information.*172* That an alarming number of ethically questionable experiments done for informational purposes—combined, perhaps, with the promise of prestige or financial gain for the investigators—shows us that “even medical progress can exact an intolerable price.”*173*

A disturbing number of recent and dangerous experiments have used vulnerable and uninformed subjects.*174* A 1966 survey by U.S. physician Henry Beecher found widespread disregard of the best interests of human subjects. *175* For example, in 1993, the Boston Globe disclosed that more than one hundred youngsters at the Fernald School for mentally disabled children were fed cereal containing radioactive isotopes during an experiment in the 1940s and 1950s.*176* In addition, from the 1950s to the 1970s, researchers infected institutionalized mentally disabled children at the Willowbrook School with hepatitis as part of a study to develop a vaccine.*177* The leading researcher, Dr. Saul Krugman of New York University, reasoned that the school’s filthy conditions would cause most new arrivals to develop the disease anyway.*178* Testimony in the ensuing trial described beaten children, maggot-infested wounds, and cruel and inappropriate use of restraints.*179*

By 1974, responding to public reaction to these and other abuses, Congress established the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research.*180* The Commission concluded that “persons having limited capacity to consent are vulnerable or disadvantaged in ways that are morally relevant to their involvement as subjects of research.”*181*

Being a person with limited capacity to consent, Petitioner Hart urges the application of this standard to her case. She asserts that, as outlined under the rules issued by the Department of Health and Human Services,*182* the Department should limit the conducting and funding of research involving greater than minimal risk on Evelyn Hart to situations where: (1) the experiments would directly benefit her, or (2) the experiment is likely to yield generalized knowledge about her own disorder.*183* These two prongs can be usefully compared with the legislation recently introduced by New Zealand as part of that nation’s acknowledgement of the unconscionability of the use of non-human hominids in research.*184*

These safeguards address the dangerous premise underlying research abuses: that ends can justify any means. Nowhere is the danger more evident than in biomedical research upon our closest living relatives. Although her class is numerically small, an understanding of Evelyn Hart’s position has wide significance, because it arises within the larger context of medical experimentation on persons. The issue is the balancing of the government’s responsibility to protect vulnerable individuals who are incapable of speaking for themselves against its goal of encouraging better methods to diagnose, treat, and otherwise care for persons. To protect Evelyn Hart is to strengthen the protections of all subjects who lack free power of choice, the legal capacity to consent, or the ability to comprehend what is happening to them.

Evelyn Hart is a person for purposes of the Fifth and the Fourteenth Constitutional Amendments. She has a demonstrable interest in remaining alive as long as life holds the possibility of enjoyment or fulfillment.*185* To incarcerate her and then to subject her to physical and psychological distress violates her fundamental rights. The burden of proof is on those who would sacrifice her interests for the general good, just as the burden of proof is on those who would sacrifice the interests of some humans to benefit others.*186* That justification must be based on more than a speculative or even marginal benefit.*187*

II. FORCING PETITIONER TO SUBMIT TO INVASIVE, NON-THERAPEUTIC RESEARCH IS REPUGNANT TO INTERNATIONAL LAW AND VIOLATES THE EIGHTH AMENDMENT TO THE CONSTITUTION OF THE UNITED STATES.

A. THE USE OF PLAINTIFF IN NON-THERAPEUTIC BIOLOGICAL EXPERIMENTS CONSTITUTES TORTURE UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW

Invasive biomedical research, when it is neither therapeutic nor voluntary, is torture. Torture can be aimed at extracting information as well as, or instead of, being designed to punish or humiliate.*188* The United Nations General Assembly has recognized a prohibition of torture under international jus cogens norms that can neither be waived nor excused.*189* Exceptional circumstances such as a state of war or any other public emergency may not be invoked as a justification.*190* Generally accepted definitions of torture appear in United Nations treaties, and underscore the worldwide interest in protecting all persons from torture and “cruel”, “inhuman,” or “degrading” treatment or punishment.*191*

Evelyn Hart, having shown that she is entitled to be classified as a person for purposes of fundamental rights, contends that the stated intentions of the National Institutes of Health constitute torture, inhuman treatment, and willful killing.*192* Enduring physical pain, confinement, isolation, overwhelming anxiety, irreversible injury, and even threats to life itself, a non-human great ape suffers as a human would suffer in similar circumstances. There is no morally or legally acceptable reason to permit the subjection of any great ape to these procedures.*193* The issue here is not whether these experiments may prove useful. The issue is whether there exist the kind of compelling circumstances that justify the severe deprivation of liberty and the physical intrusions involved in such experiments.*194*

Finally, bodily intrusion should not be permitted where there is no possibility of benefiting the subject of the intrusion.*195* Here, no benefit is being sought for non-human great apes themselves. This Court’s recognition of Evelyn Hart’s personhood would bar the imposition of invasive, nonconsensual procedures upon her, just as the law now prohibits such impositions upon humans.

B. THE GOVERNMENT’S PLAN OFFENDS U.S. OBLIGATIONS UNDER INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE EIGHTH AMENDMENT TO THE U.S. CONSTITUTION

1. The United States recognizes international norms prohibiting torture.

The United States recognizes that international law prohibits torture, under The Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture (the “Torture Convention”).*196* The United States has ratified the Torture Convention;*197* thus, under Article VI of the Constitution, it is the supreme law of the land. The Torture Convention embodies an essential principle of international legal norms. Theodor Meron recognizes the “irreducible core” of four fundamental rights: “the right to life and the prohibitions of slavery, torture and retroactive penal measures.”*198*

Freedom from torture has been treated as a fundamental legal right under domestic as well as international law.*199* International law is directly enforceable through the Supremacy Clause of the United States Constitution,*200* which ensures that ratified treaties become part of the supreme law of the United States, equal in status to a federal statute.*201*

2. The Eighth Amendment may acquire meaning as public opinion becomes enlightened by a humane justice, and is broad enough to prohibit the act of torture.

Not only has the United States ratified the Torture Convention;*202* torture is also repugnant to the Eighth Amendment.*203* Although the Eighth Amendment refers only to punishment, the Supreme Court in In re Kemmler held that the Eighth Amendment does indeed prohibit torture.*204*

In Weems v. United States, the Supreme Court noted that the Eighth Amendment may be “progressive, and is not fastened to the obsolete but may acquire meaning as public opinion becomes enlightened by a humane justice.”*205* For example, a majority of the Court indicated that “deliberate indifference to serious medical needs” of prisoners would violate the Eighth Amendment.*206*

In Trop v. Dulles, *207* the Court observed that “evolving standards of decency that mark the progress of a maturing society” should inform interpretation of the Eighth Amendment.*208*

The prohibition of cruel and unusual punishment has always focused on the right to be free from physical and mental torture. Recalling Kafka’s story The Penal Colony, Professor Tribe wrote that “even the most awful tortures, it must be remembered, can be cloaked with such clockwork logic that many become persuaded of their perverse justice.”*209* The Court has addressed “serious constitutional questions respecting cruel and unusual punishment” in a case in which a prisoner was alleged to have been forced into medical and psychological experimentation.*210* If cruel and unusual punishment of convicted prisoners is forbidden by the United States Constitution, then, it is hard to find any principle permitting cruel and unusual punishment of innocent individuals.*211*

3. This case should be heard and decided, because Evelyn Hart’s cause of action reflects important ways in which international law influences the scope of protections against abuses under national law in state and federal courts.

In the early nineteenth century, in Foster v. Neilson, *212* the Supreme Court introduced a significant restraint on the application of treaties in domestic law: the doctrine of self-execution.*213* The Court held that a treaty is directly implementable in the United States only if “it operates of itself without the aid of any legislative provision.”*214* In determining whether a treaty may be deemed self-executing, the Third Restatement of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States advises courts to consider the intent of the signatory parties, and any statements that the executive or legislative branches made concerning the treaty.*215* Some international legal scholars, however, have argued that United States courts neglect their duty under the Supremacy Clause if they do not faithfully implement the terms of a ratified treaty.*216* The issue of whether human rights clauses of the United Nations are self-executing in the United States, once ratified, is unsettled.

The International Court of Justice has ruled that the human rights provisions of the United Nations Charter impose binding obligations on all United Nations member states.*217* The Supreme Court of California, however, in Sei Fujii v. State, *218* ruled that articles 55(c) and 56 of the United Nations Charter, which stipulate that member nations will promote the observance of human rights without discriminating on the basis of race, could not form the basis of a suit absent domestic implementing legislation.*219* Former California Supreme Court Judge Frank Newman has pointed out that subsequently ratified United Nations treaties such as the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR) contain a degree of specificity not found in the United Nations Charter, increasing the likelihood that those subsequent treaties are self-executing.*220*

Although The Vienna Convention recognizes that states may enter a reservation when ratifying a particular provision of a treaty unless the reservation is incompatible with the object and purpose of the treaty,*221* some treaty provisions are considered so fundamental that no limitations can be contemplated in their ratification.*222* It is this non-derogability that distinguishes a peremptory from a customary norm.*223* A norm retains its peremptory character so long as a substantial majority of nations recognize it.*224* Peremptory norms include “gross violations of human rights” such as torture.*225*

Torture is expressly or implicitly prohibited by the constitutions of more than fifty-five nations,*226* including this one through the Eighth Amendment.*227* Chief Justice Marshall stated that when acts are proscribed by the law of nations, such prohibitions are binding on the United States courts.*228*

This case should be heard and decided, because Hart’s claim flows directly from the United States ratification of the Torture Convention, and her cause of action can be addressed through her substantive right as embodied in the Eighth amendment. International Law and the Eighth Amendment operate no less than the Fourteenth Amendment to afford protection to legal persons. Evelyn Hart requests a prohibition of the treatment planned by the government and the University, because that treatment constitutes torture, and because in the context of both the Eighth Amendment and International Law, Petitioner meets the definition of a person entitled to legal protection.

IV. FORCING THE PETITIONER TO SUBMIT TO CONFINEMENT AND BIOMEDICAL RESEARCH VIOLATES THE THIRTEENTH AMENDMENT’S REPUDIATION OF SLAVERY

A. TREATMENT OF NON-HUMAN GREAT APES AS CHATTELS IS REPUGNANT BOTH TO THE SPIRIT AND PURPOSE OF THE THIRTEENTH CONSTITUTIONAL AMENDMENT

From time to time, the legal meaning of “person” has had to be revised to include someone who had been excluded. Former slaves and their descendants were accorded personhood because sensitivities changed, so that what had become socially abhorrent became legally intolerable. As a society, we observed that the essence of slavery is the assignment of a lower valuation to individuals based upon morally arbitrary characteristics. Enslaved individuals are valued as mere commodities rather than as persons, who must have the higher valuation of respect.*229*

When non-human great apes are treated as objects to be bought and sold, their unique individual natures and capacities are subverted to the purposes of others. They are enslaved. Our knowledge of the capacities of the non-human great apes demands a serious and urgent reconsideration of their inclusion in the legal category “property.”

Recategorization of this kind is not without precedent. In 1865, the Thirteenth Constitutional Amendment pronounced that “[n]either slavery nor involuntary servitude, except as punishment for a crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted, shall exist within the United States, or any place subject to their jurisdiction.”*230* With that announcement, an entire class of individuals was legally relocated from the category called “property” to the category called “person.” For it was not nature that made their class into property; it was law, and it was law that changed their classification.*231* Discussing the impact of this legal development on U.S. property law, Justice Swayne wrote in 1866:

The thirteenth amendment…[t]renches directly upon the powers of the states and of the people of the states…It destroyed the most important relation between capital and labor in all the states where slavery existed. It affected deeply the fortunes of a large portion of their people. It struck out of existence millions of property. The measure was the consequence of a strife of opinions and a conflict of interests, real or imaginary, as old as the constitution itself.*232*

The lead of the Thirteenth Amendment was not immediately followed throughout the nation. In the case of the General Rucker,*233* a boat worker with a skull injury explained to the court how the mate of the boat beat him with a tool until he fell overboard.*234* The mate forced him back to work by threatening to shoot him. Judge Hammond opined, “Of course it is possible that this negro man of inferior intelligence conceived the idea…of taking advantage of the circumstance that in falling he had cut his head to wholly fabricate a story…[but] it was well said by the learned counsel of libelant that these simple-minded negroes are scarcely equal to such a scheme as that.”*235* The Judge surmised that this mate was “pursuing the usual method—to which they are nearly all addicted, and which they dislike to give up—of enforcing obedience to his orders by physical force…It is fairly to be inferred that…the mate was engaged in driving the hands to the speedy work necessary to enable the boat to leave that evening, and …he tapped him on the head with the monkey-wrench…severely enough to make an ugly wound…”*236*

A modern reader will recoil at the thought that beating people was a common addiction, and that the plaintiff could be assaulted yet again in court by the prejudice apparent in the judge’s derisive handling of his case. Sadly, the pernicious “addiction” to cruelty plays out today, but the most blatant examples include those of humans enforcing their will upon non-human “workers.” There is an uncanny parallel between the beating of the ship worker “by the usual method” and the treatment of non-human great apes in profit-making ventures. We saw an example of this when a dancer in a Las Vegas nightclub videotaped widely-known ape “trainer” Bobby Berosini back-stage before the beginning of his show.*237* The tape shows Berosini, immediately before going on stage, grabbing, slapping, punching, and shaking orang-utans while several handlers hold the animals in position.*238* The tape also shows Berosini striking the animals with a rod.*239* At least nine separate incidents were taped in the short period between the 9th and the 16th of July, 1989.*240*

Aristotle considered slavery an intolerable condition—for Greeks.*241* On the other hand, he believed that the physical characteristics of some living beings made them slaves by “nature”:*242*

…so is it naturally with the male and the female; the one is superior, the other inferior; the one governs, the other is governed; and the same rule must necessarily hold good with respect to all mankind. Those men therefore who are as much inferior to others as the body is to the soul, are to be thus disposed of, as the proper use of them is their bodies, in which their excellence consists; and if what I have said be true, they are slaves by nature, and it is advantageous to them to be always under government. He then is by nature formed a slave who is qualified to become the chattel of another person, and on that account is so, and who has just reason enough to know that there is such a faculty, without being indued of the use of it; for other animals have no perception of reason, but are entirely guided by appetite, and indeed they vary very little in their use from each other; for the advantage which we receive, both from slaves and tame animals, arises from their bodily strength administering to our necessities…*243*

Modern society can no longer justify treating some humans as “slaves by nature.” Given what we now know about non-human great apes, slavery is every bit as intolerable when imposed upon them. Geza Teleki provides accounts of the modern chimpanzee trade, explaining that at least ten chimpanzees die for every young one that survives more than one year at the overseas destination.*244* The details are shockingly reminiscent of the methods of the human slave trade:

Most prized by the dealers and their clients are nursing infants who are less than two years of age and totally dependent on their mothers for survival. The slaughter begins in the wilderness as hunters with shotguns or flintlocks loaded with pebbles or metal shrapnel attack mothers and other protective group members. Many infants die when this crude ammunition scatters to hit both mothers and their clinging offspring. Pit traps, poisoned food, wire snares, nets and even dog packs are also used to kill adults defending the youngsters. More deaths occur during transport to villages. Infants are often tied hand and foot with wire, causing circulation loss and septic wounds, and are trucked to urban centres in tiny cages or tightly bound sacks, often under heavy suffocating loads to avoid detection at checkpoints. Few receive care en route, so starvation and dehydration are commonplace. While awaiting shipment overseas, more die of neglect in filthy holding pens and at airports where flight delays lead to exposure. Cramped in tiny crates, even carried in personal luggage, the victims often must endure days of travel through several transit points which offer ample opportunities for falsifying documentation. Some infants manage, against all odds, to survive this ordeal only to die at the final destinations from cumulative physical and psychological trauma.*245*

Shaking in cages, ravaged by malnutrition, negligently or deliberately injured by handlers, the young chimpanzees who survive are brought to dealers who sell them to private collectors for thousands of dollars each.*246*

Similarly, international investors put up considerable sums of money to trade in humans.*247*Historians estimate that between thirty and sixty million Africans were caught up in fours centuries of slave trade, but most did not survive the march to the ships, the wait in holding stations or the voyage itself:*248*

On many of these ships, the sense of misery and suffocation was so terrible in the ’tween-decks—where the height was only 18 inches, so that the unfortunate slaves could not turn round, were wedged immovably, . . . and chained to the deck by the neck and legs—that the slaves not infrequently would go mad before dying or suffocating.*249*

Cases heard prior to the passage of the Thirteenth Amendment give us an idea of how slaves were bought and sold. In an 1848 court document valuing “certain goods and chattels,”*250* each adult male, regardless of listed skill, was valued at $2,000.*251* Each woman was valued at $1,000, including “one negro woman, a tanner by trade, and skilful therein.”*252* Children were appraised at $500.*253*

Enslavement transcended economics. It quashed autonomy and the most basic individual dignity. Slave families were broken up at court sales in order to release more capital.*254* Neither slave marriages nor parental relationships had legal standing.*255*

Although slaves had no recourse to the law, the law could be applied to terrorize them. For runaways, laws encouraged scalping, whipping, branding, amputations, castrations, (via a statute providing a slave “shall be gelt”), and death.*256* Virginia law exculpated whites for homicide of slaves.*257* In response to a 1712 insurrection, New York judges sentenced twenty-five slaves to death.*258* Three were sentenced to be burned at the stake — “one by slow fire in torment for eight to ten hours and until consumed by ashes; one to be broken on the wheel and so languish until dead; and one to be hung in chains without sustenance until dead.”*259* One of the convicted was pregnant; her sentence was reprieved until she had given birth; then she was hanged.*260*

How on earth were these acts justified in the minds of those who carried them out? The rationale for such monumental atrocities had to be accumulated over a vast period of time.*261*

The ancient concept of the Great Chain of Being ranked creation from inanimate forms such as rocks, to plants, to non-human animals, to humans, to the many ranks of heavenly creatures, with God at the pinnacle.*262* The “lowest” humans ranked just over the “highest” non-human animal, presumably simian.*263* This mythical Chain “universalize[d] the principle of hierarchy.”*264* Carolus Linnaeus elaborated on the principle, in his Systema Naturae. *265* Although all humans appeared within the category of Homo Sapiens, Linneaus divided them into seven variations: American, European, Asiatic, African, wild men, Monstrosus, and Troglodytes.*266* In the 1770s, Dutch anatomist Peter Camper found in his collection of skulls a “facial angle” that revealed a gradation of similarity starting from non-human apes and continuing through Africans to Europeans.*267*

The theory that races of humans are separate species appears in philosopher David Hume’s division of humans according to his opinion of their cultural merits:

I am apt to suspect the negroes, and in general all the other species of men (for there are four or five different kinds) to be naturally inferior to the whites. There never was a civilized nation of any other complexion than white, nor even any individual eminent either in action or speculation. No ingenious manufactures amongst them, no arts, no sciences.”*268*

In other words, Africans were to be subjected to grotesque abuse because they were considered less than human by those who wished to popularize a certain worldview. Racism, in its origins, was speciesism.

Modern scholarly debate has sought the origins of the “law of slavery.” Slave law can be regarded as a social custom congealed into legal precedent.*269* This principle was used to legitimate slavery by British courts*270* and the United States Supreme Court.*271*

The British government recognized slavery in the colonies as an object of both private and public international law by the nineteenth century,*272* providing one of the most stable foundations for the legitimacy of slavery in the United States.*273* South Carolina derived the legal precedent for lifetime, race-based slavery from seventeenth century Barbadian laws.*274* Although some ostensibly “welfarist” legislation was extended,*275* historian Winthrop Jordan called Carolina’s slavery “the most rigorous deprivation of freedom to exist in institutionalized form anywhere in the English continental colonies.”*276*

By the mid-1700s, slaves were definitively categorized as chattels.*277* In 1641, Massachusetts adopted the Body of Liberties, which cited “the law of God” to differentiate between free people and those permitted to be enslaved.*278* The framers incorporated the detailed regulations in Leviticus 25:39-55, including the distinction between “your brethren the children of Israel”*279* and “the heathen that are round about you.”*280* Theophilus Eaton, a founder of the New Haven colony, claimed to own Africans in 1658 as “servants forever or during his pleasure, according to Leviticus, 25: 45 and 46.”*281*

The year of 1705 saw Virginia’s first comprehensive slave “code.”*282* Africans were deemed more economical than white servants, because the planters and government were willing to control them with measures they considered too extreme to impose on other English people.*283* Virginia’s leaders banned lifetime enslavement of Christian people, implicitly limiting slavery to Africans and Native Americans.*284*

Slavery, then, entered into law gradually, yet through deliberate legislation. By entering the realm of property relationships, slaves were diminished considerably from human stature, by the operation of law. They became the objects of inheritances, creditors’ rights, warranty, life estates and mortgages.*285* They were subjects of import duties and property taxes.*286* Any initial claim to free status and of legal protection of inherent basic rights was invisible by the early eighteenth century.*287* Commercial implications of the developments in exploitation of human beings became fully evident just before the Civil War, by which time corporations had begun to own slaves.*288*

The case of Dred Scott and his family held that descendants of emancipated slaves were not “citizens” of the several states at the adoption of the Constitution.*289* There was more. Slaves and their descendants, free or not, were not “acknowledged as a part of the people, nor intended to be….”*290*Chief Justice Roger B. Taney stated as the reason for their exclusion that: “they had for more than a century before been regarded as beings… so far inferior that they had no rights which the white man was bound to respect, and that the negro might justly and lawfully be reduced to slavery for his benefit;” that a slave was “bought and sold, and treated as an ordinary article of merchandise and traffic, whenever a profit could be made by it;” and that this opinion was at that time fixed and universal in the civilized portion of the white race. It was regarded as an axiom in morals as well as in politics, which no one thought of disputing, or supposed to be open to dispute, and men in every grade and position in society daily and habitually acted upon it in their private pursuits, as well as in matters of public concern, without doubting for a moment the correctness of this opinion.*291*

We now know that the society based upon the supposed moral inferiority of human slaves was based on dangerous illusions. As a result, constitutional law has since been amended. The idea of moral inferiority of women to men has likewise been outgrown.*292*

Industrial society, with its increasingly sophisticated knowledge in social and scientific fields, has neither belief in nor use for involuntary servitude. Contemporary scientific knowledge is demonstrating the connection between ourselves and our fellow great apes at the same time that new techniques render our use of the non-human great apes in research unnecessary.

The prohibition of slavery is already part of our Constitution. Therefore, no Constitutional Amendment is needed for Evelyn Hart and her class.

B. EVEN POTENTIAL SUCCESSES IN MEDICAL RESEARCH DO NOT SUMMARILY JUSTIFY THE SUBJECTION OF A CLASS TO NON-CONSENTUAL EXPERIMENTATION

The use of human slaves in medical experimentation was widespread,*293* and the techniques applied blur the line between research and torture, as evidenced by the following examples. Dr. Thomas Hamilton’s search for a remedy for sunstroke involved placing a slave in an open-pit oven in rural Georgia.*294* J. Marion Sims repeatedly performed painful surgery on twenty-six Alabama slave women who needed treatment, but underwent surgery without anaesthesia despite its availability.*295* In 1849, after the thirtieth operation on his first subject, Sims found a cure for vesico-vaginal fistulae.*296* The arguments advanced to justify such experiments are the same as those used to defend research on the Petitioner in this case: the quest for advances in medicine.

Where slaves were used, medical experimentation appears to have worked. For example, Thomas Jefferson personally conducted smallpox vaccination experiments on his slaves, and his efforts met with success.*297* Some such experiments surely increased life expectancies in the United States, but the price paid by the slaves was often irreversible damage, or death.*298* As Justice Ross of the New York Supreme Court wrote in a modern case involving subjects who were involuntarily hospitalized at various psychiatric institutions:

The benefits of, and needs for, the medical research at issue are clear and evident; but at what cost in human pain and suffering to those subjects who are not capable of expressing either their consent or objection to participation? …[H]owever laudable the ends which defendants seek to achieve may be, those results must be gained through means within their grant of authority and which properly safeguard the rights of the plaintiffs. It may very well be that for some categories of greater than minimal risk non-therapeutic experiments, devised to achieve a future benefit, there is at present no constitutionally acceptable protocol for obtaining the participation of incapable individuals…The alternative of allowing such experiments to continue, without proper consent and in violation of the rights of the incapable individuals who participate, is clearly unacceptable.*299*

Thus, even where results are perceived to have considerable value, the core problem remains unaffected: namely, the disregard for the violation of the individual’s right to give or to withhold consent. Concern for the well being of potential subjects, the paramount concern in the treatment setting, must also be the overriding concern in research. To disregard this principle is to lead society down a dangerous path.

V. SANCTUARY IS AN APPROPRIATE ANSWER FOR THE SPECIFIC CIRCUMSTANCES OF PETITIONER’S CASE

Once we have recognized an individual’s claim to certain basic rights, the next step is to frame a system in which these rights can and will be meaningfully enforced. As Ronald Dworkin has put the point, “Any plausible interpretation of the rights people have under the Constitution must be complex enough to speak to the remedy as well as the substance.”*300*

In the case of non-human great apes, once the immorality of capturing them from their habitat and/or forcing them to breed in captivity is appreciated, and then recognized by the law, there remains the practical issues of how we are to treat those non-human hominids already living in the U.S. In discussions about liberty, the idea of “benign captivity” of non-human great apes in zoos and other institutions that are designed for human education or entertainment is sometimes advanced.*301* Some zoos and educational institutions maintain healthy great ape populations for scientific study.*302* The message this conveys is that human education is more important than the freedom of non-human great apes. The zoo, like the laboratory, benefits from the unexamined assumption that the liberty interests of nonhuman great apes matter so little that their confinement is appropriate.

Despite the demeaning implications of captivity, there may be instances in which some form of confinement of non-human great apes is necessary, particularly when an individual has become so conditioned to life away from her natural habitat that survival in true freedom is not possible. In such a case, confinement in a sanctuary is appropriate.*303* A decision that confinement is in the best interest of the individual does not mean that public exhibition is also warranted.

One commentator, on the issue of constitutional privacy rights, referred to “sanctuary” as an element of privacy that involves “protection against intrusive observation.”*304* Because each chimpanzee, gorilla, bonobo, and orang-utan is a unique and complex personality, each situation should be assessed in terms of the individual whose life and future is being considered.*305*

Evelyn Hart, like some other great apes in similar situations, cannot regain her freedom by returning to Africa. Many non-human great apes who have lived in captivity lack the skills necessary for survival in the wild; moreover, the return journey would be physically and psychologically hazardous.*306* Often, as in this case, a private sanctuary may present the best answer.*307* Evelyn Hart’s guardian, Professor Robin Lane, has specified the Fauna Foundation sanctuary as the preferred destination. The sanctuary has made arrangements for her to become a permanent resident.

CONCLUSION

From time to time, but not too often, society as a whole must admit that it was wrong. Collectively, we grow out of certain habits of mind, certain modes of behavior. Examples abound, but human slavery and its abolition is a familiar example as is, more recently, the end of apartheid in South Africa. When the collective prejudices, or unexamined assumptions, which have shaped a particular set of laws are later shown to be wrong—morally wrong, perhaps, as a result of changed morality; factually wrong, perhaps, in light of advances in our knowledge—the right response is for the law to take account of the changed morality, or the new knowledge, or, as in this case, both. We now know that it was wrong to classify Evelyn Hart, and others like her, as property. The law as it now stands cannot be defended, save as a product of the ignorance of its time.

But even recognizing and accepting our moral obligation to the Evelyn Harts in this country does not conclude our inquiry. The next question we must ask is whether the practical consequences of affording Evelyn Hart the minimal protections she seeks would be so far reaching, so disruptive of the status quo, as to render the idea infeasible. Let us look, then, at the consequences. We may assume that if there were a well organized, well funded group opposed to protecting non-human great apes, we would be treated to a parade of horrors. “Next President Could Be A Chimpanzee,” the New York Post might proclaim. “Orang-utans To Get Drivers’ Licences?” asks the New York Times, reporting that “people on the street worry that it will be difficult to determine which rights non human great apes do have, and which they do not. ‘I don’t want come in one day and find that I’ve been replaced by an orang-utan,’ observed Anil Khan, a driver with the Yellow Cab Company.”

There are at least two good answers to this anticipated parade of horrors. The first is that a moral imperative is just that: imperative. Worldwide condemnation of apartheid and resultant pressure for its abolition were not, in the main, tempered or restrained by questions of practicality. The fact of the moral imperative was enough. And so it is here. The second answer to the parade of horrors is that they bear no relation to what Petitioner is asking of this Court. She is asking, quite simply, for the same fundamental protections as are afforded other persons. This Court can, of course, grant Petitioner rudimentary protections against physical and psychological harm without also being understood to have granted her the right to vote, to drive, or to hold public office. To be free from abuse, and to be free to accept the sanctuary being offered her: that is all she is asking.

Evelyn Hart has answered the philosophic objection that there can be no rights without duties. The answer is two-fold. First, as a matter of law, there is nothing novel about protecting those in need without imposing a countervailing obligation on them. Youngberg v. Romeo demonstrates that United States law can recognize rights commensurate with a Plaintiff’s needs and capacities, despite the fact that there may be no correlative responsibilities imposed.*308* Second, although one consequence of this reclassification—from Property to Person—is that arrangements must be made for her care, we would do well to remember how she came to be “property”in the first place. We have invaded, disrupted, and largely destroyed her world, for our purposes.*309* Therefore, if non-human great apes who were long ago captured in the wild, enslaved, and shipped here, are no longer able to fend for themselves in what was their natural habitat, the very least we can do is to provide safe and peaceful sanctuary.

A primary purpose of justice is to correct “the arbitrariness of the world.”*310* The plight of Evelyn Hart demonstrates that such arbitrariness is not limited to human relations. But here, the arbitrariness is of human making. For all of these reasons, the Petitioner respectfully requests this Court to reverse the judgment of the District of Columbia Circuit of the Court of Appeals, and to enjoin the National Institutes of Health from assuming ownership of her.


ATTACHMENT: THE DECLARATION ON GREAT APES*311*

We demand the extension of the community of equals to include all great apes: human beings, chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas and orang-utans. The community of equals is the moral community within which we accept certain basic moral principles or rights as governing our relations with each other and enforceable at law. Among these principles or rights are the following:

I. The Right to Life

The lives of members of the community of equals are to be protected. Members of the community of equals may not be killed except in very strictly defined circumstances, for example, self-defence.

II. The Protection of Individual Liberty*312*

Members of the community of equals are not to be arbitrarily deprived of their liberty; if they should be imprisoned without due legal process, they have the right to immediate release. The detention of those who have not been convicted of any crime, or of those who are not criminally liable, should be allowed only where it can be shown to be for their own good, or necessary to protect the public from a member of the community who would clearly be a danger to others if at liberty. In such cases, members of the community of equals must have the right to appeal, either directly or, if they lack the relevant capacity, through an advocate, to a judicial tribunal.

III. The Prohibition of Torture

The deliberate infliction of severe pain on a member of the community of equals, either wantonly or for an alleged benefit to others, is regarded as torture, and is wrong.


FOOTNOTES

Fna. Lee Hall (J.D., 1999, University of Maryland; B.A., 1983, Northwestern University) is a lawyer in Baltimore. Anthony Jon Waters (B.A., 1972, University of Keele; LL.M., 1974, Yale University) is Visiting Professor of Law at the University of Oregon School of Law and Professor of Law at the University of Maryland School of Law.

FNaa. The authors thank Gordon G. Young, Professor at University of Maryland’s School of Law, who inspired us to transform our intuitions about basic principles of law into the legal arguments contained in this brief. As our knowledge of this subject evolves, Professor Young continues to provide guidance, references, and an exemplary model of personhood. We also respectfully thank Paula Casal, Paola Cavalieri, Maxwell O. Chibundu, Andrew Timothy Fenton, Gary L. Francione, Dietrich von Haugwitz, Diane Hoffmann, Peter Singer, David Sztybel, and Andrew D. Williams for their expertise and encouragement. We thank Jane Goodall for advising on factual questions relating to chimpanzees. Michael Maccini provided research and technical assistance. Anthony Smith of the Fauna Foundation graciously introduced us to fifteen chimpanzees, who subsequently allowed us to get to know them as persons.

*1* See generally The Great Ape Project: Equality Beyond Humanity (Paola Cavalieri & Peter Singer, eds., 1994) (an anthology of the scholarship elucidating its opening sentence, “We are human, and we are also great apes”). Whereas species were once were classified simply by outward appearance, today’s sophisticated tools, such as DNA profiling and genetic mapping, permit accurate measurement both of variances and fundamental similarities among beings. See Jared Diamond, The Third Chimpanzee, in The Great Ape Project, supra, at 93-96. Chimpanzees are more closely related to humans than to gorillas; Frans de Waal, director of the Living Links Project on human evolution at Yerkes, Atlanta, indicates the 98.4 percent overlap in DNA between humans and chimpanzees and bonobos as a salient factor in extrapolating scientific data among them. See Richard Saltus, Scientists Plot Road Map of Human DNA, The New Orleans Times-Picayune, June 27, 2000, at A01.

*2* See generally Richard Byrne, The Thinking Ape: Evolutionary Origins of Intelligence (1995) (illustrating that Pan troglodytes, Gorilla gorilla, Pan paniscus, and Homo sapiens are all species of African great apes; and that, together with Pongo pygmaeus, they are members of a slightly larger taxonomic group known as the great apes, or “hominoidea”).It is interesting to learn, however, that the most recent edition of the Smithsonian’s definitive classification, Mammal Species of the World, has moved the non-human great apes into the family Homindae, previously reserved for humans alone. Mammal Species of the World (D. Wilson & D.M. Reeder, eds., 2d ed. 1993).

*3* Steve F. Sapontzis, Morals Reason, and Animals 67 (1987). Sapontzis has defined “person” simply as any being who can and should have moral rights.

*4* The law that currently regulates the use and treatment of all non-humans is obviously based upon a Cartesian ethology. The Cartesian view (i.e., the view of French philosopher René Descartes) holds that animals are unfeeling automatons, devoid of sentience and emotion. See generally, Political Theory & Animal Rights 14-17 (Paul A.V. Clarke & Andrew Linzey eds., 1990). Thus, Descartes advanced the theory that nonhuman animals were merely unfeeling machines. See id.

*5* See Sapontzis, supra note 3, at 38.

*6* Christopher D. Stone, Should Trees Have Standing? Toward Legal Rights for Natural Objects 8 (1974) (citations omitted) (emphasis in original).

*7* John Stuart Mill, On Liberty 125-26 (1859).

*8* UK Bans Experiments on Great Apes, Bridging the GAP: Newsletter of the Great Ape Project International, Autumn/Winter 1997 Extra, http://www.greatapeproject.org/newsletters/BtG2xtra.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*9* John Luxton, New Zealand’s Minister for Food and Fibre, stated, “This requirement recognizes the advanced cognitive and emotional capacity of great apes.” Peter Singer, New Zealand Takes the First Step, Bridging the GAP: Newsletter of the Great Ape Project International, Autumn/Winter 1999, Issue 3, http://www.greatapeproject.org/newsletters/btg991.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*10* A further question might be asked: if our legal system of rights could encompass the non-human great apes without social upheaval, what if baboons or dolphins can also be shown to be self-aware, reasoning beings? Clearly, it would be wrong to deny one group of persons their rights simply because another group might also be entitled to them. Although we we cannot say with certainty that no other non-human animals are self-aware, rational, or otherwise endowed with the chararteristics of personhood, the tremendous complexity of great apes’ lives, including their ability to communicate, their social structures and emotional repertoires, are now well-known and scientifically established.

*11* See generally Thane Maynard, Primates: Apes, Monkeys, Prosimians (Franklin Watts ed., 1994). Chimpanzees live north of the Zaïre River, from Tanzania west to Senegal. Bonobos, inaccurately called “pygmy chimpanzees,” inhabit the swamp forests of central Zaïre. Id. Mountain gorillas live in Zaïre, Rwanda, and Uganda; and lowland gorillas inhabit central and west Africa, from the rainforest of the Atlantic coastal nations of Cameroon, Equatorial Guinea, and Gabon, east along the equator through Congo, Central African Republic, and eastern Zaïre. Id. Orang-utans are now found only in Borneo and Sumatra. Id. (Zaïre was renamed The Democratic Republic of Congo on May 17, 1997, as explained in Rebellion as a way of life: Congo/Zaire’s bloody history, Agence France Press, June 29, 2000. We retain the former name to avoid confusion, given its neighbor country which has the same name).

*12* Recognition of non-human apes’ constitutional interests would conceivably have an indirect benefit for apes in their natural habitat: the incentive to capture free-living apes, at least for the purpose of sale to dealers within the United States, would be removed.

*13* Cass R. Sunstein, An Eighteenth Century Presidency in a Twenty-First Century World, 48 Ark. L. Rev. 1, 21 (1994).

*14* See Toshiba Nishida, Chimpanzees are Always New to Me, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 26.

*15* 405 U.S. 727 (1972).

*16* 504 U.S. 555 (1992).

*17* Although the Animal Welfare Act was designed to insure humane treatment, non-human subjects of biomedical research are often kept in cramped spaces where isolation, repeated handling, physical pain and injury are routine. For a detailed treatment of this issue, see Laura G. Kniaz, Animal Liberation and the Law: Animals Board the Underground Railroad, 43 Buff L. Rev. 765, 789-92 (1995).

*18* Courts have read Article III, §2 of the Constitution as restricting federal courts to disputes “traditionally thought to be capable of resolution through judicial process.” Sierra Club v. Morton, 405 U.S. 727, 732 (1972); Flast v. Cohen, 392 U.S. 83, 101 (1968). Under the current doctrine of “standing,” federal litigants must demonstrate (1) injury in fact; (2) which is caused by, or is fairly traceable to, alleged unlawful conduct; and (3) which is likely to be redressed by favorable decision of the court. Fla. Audubon Soc’y v. Bentsen, 94 F.3d 658, 662-63 (D.C. Cir. 1996); Valley Forge Christian College v. Ams. United, 454 U.S. 464, 472 (1982). A party invoking judicial review in the hope of striking down legislation must show that the statute is invalid and that she has sustained or is immediately in danger of sustaining some direct injury as the result of its enforcement, and not a generalized grievance. Lujan v. Defenders of Wildlife, 504 U.S. 555, 601 (1992). This ensures that the Court does not “assume a position of authority over the governmental acts of another and co-equal department. Id. For prudential standing, a plaintiff must additionally show that “‘the interest sought to be protected by the complainant is arguably within the zone of interests to be protected or regulated by the statute.’” Hazardous Waste Treatment Council v. EPA, 861 F.2d 277, 282 (D.C. Cir. 1988) (citing Ass’n of Data Processing Serv. Org., Inc. v. Camp, 397 U.S. 150, 153 (1970)). The test is whether Congress “intended for [a particular] class [of plaintiffs] to be relied upon to challenge the agency disregard of the law.” Clarke v. Securities Indus. Ass’n, 479 U.S. 388, 399 (1987) (citation omitted). Congress is deemed to have intended to preclude the general public from bringing an action where oversight bodies known as Institutional Animal Care and Use Committees (“IACUCs”) have been installed with the express purpose of ensuring the public interest that AWA minimum standards are met. See Int’l Primate Prot. League v. Adm’rs of the Tulane Educ. Fund, 895 F.2d 1056, 1058-59 (5th Cir. 1990).

*19* 895 F.2d 1056 (5th Cir. 1990). In Int’l Primate Protection League, groups and individuals sought custody of non-human primates who were then controlled by a scientist who had been charged with multiple counts of animal cruelty under Maryland state law. Id. The federal court held that the Plaintiffs lacked standing under Article III. Id. at 1058-59. This holding was in alignment with the view of the Fourth Circuit’s previous affirmation of the District Court’s dismissal of the case. Judge Wilkinson of the Fourth Circuit stated: “In fact, we are persuaded that Congress intended that the independence of medical research be respected and that administrative enforcement govern the Animal Welfare Act.” Int’l Primate Prot. League v. Inst. for Behavioral Research, Inc., 799 F.2d 934, 935 (4th Cir.1986). Deference to the independence of medical research is deference to an entity that cannot be expected to act disinterestedly in the matter. Such deference is not appropriately exercised in the case of research subjects who are persons. Acknowledging that Evelyn Hart’s interests merit judicial protection might seem more difficult than merely deferring to legislative wisdom; as Professor Tribe writes, “it always looks more legitimate, at first glance, to defer to others. But even that may entail an assumption of power, especially when the decision maker exercises discretion in deciding when to defer and when to intervene, as the Court obviously has done ever since Marbury v. Madison.” Laurence H. Tribe, Unraveling National League of Cities: The New Federalism and Affirmative Rights to Essential Government Services, 90 Harv. L. Rev. 1065, 1087 (1977).

*20* See Animal Legal Defense Fund, Inc. v. Glickman, 130 F.3d 464 (D.C. Cir. 1997); Animal Legal Defense Fund, Inc. v. Nat’l Ass. for Biomedical Research, 136 F.3d 829 (D.C. Cir. 1998). The Animal Welfare Act (AWA) mandates establishment of IACUCs at research sites that use animals covered under the Act. See 7 U.S.C. § 2143(b)(1) (1994). See also David R. Schmahmann & Lori J. Polacheck, The Case Against Rights for Animals, 22 B.C. Envtl. Aff. L. Rev. 747, 765-68 (1995) (claiming that the Animal Welfare Act codifies the human right to use non-humans in research).

*21* See U.S. Const. art. III, § 2.

*22* Francis J. Novembre of Emory University’s Yerkes laboratory presents an example of a scientist who prefers to refer to chimpanzees by serial number rather than by name. See Abstract of Project No.5 R01 AI40879-02, Emory University, http://www.ncrr.nih.gov/grants/crisp.html (visited August 11, 1998). The abstract reports, “At the time that C499 developed illness, blood was transfused from this animal to an uninfected animal, C455, to further examine the pathogenesis of virus infection.” Id. Novembre was avoiding saying that before Jerom (C499) died, he was forcibly paralyzed with a drug so that some of his blood could be taken. Then his blood was injected into Nathan (C455) to see if he would also become sick and die. Id.

*23* Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 155 (1973). *24* U.S Const. amend. V; U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1.

*25* U.S. Const. amend. XIII, § 1.

*26-27* See Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. at 124.

*28* See Joseph Vining, Legal Identity: The Coming of Age of Public Law 144 (1978).

*29-30* Laurence H. Tribe, American Constitutional Law §15-3, at 1308 (2d ed. 1988).

*31* The point, however, cannot be stated with absolute certainty. Frans de Waal, a primatologist at the Yerkes Regional Primate Center in Atlanta, U.S., felt compelled to describe the ape personalities and politics he observed in human terms, stating that they “can only be portrayed accurately by using the same adjectives as we use to characterize our fellow human beings.” H. Lyn White Miles, Language and the Orang-utan: The Old ‘Person’ of the Forest, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 43.

*32* See generally Jane Goodall, The Chimpanzees of Gombe (1990).

*33* After more than three decades of studying chimpanzees, Dr. Jane Goodall affirms that our closest living relatives are so similar to us that they feel pain and suffering in much the same way that we do. See Jane Goodall,Chimpanzees – Bridging the Gap, The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 13.

*34* See, e.g., Jane Goodall, Tool Using and Aimed Throwing in a Community of Free-Living Chimpanzees, 201 Nature 1264-1266 (1964).

*35* See, e.g., Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677, 684 (1973) (invalidating sex discrimination by a State, observing that the “attitude of ‘romantic paternalism’ … put women, not on a pedestal, but in a cage”).

*36* Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Emipire 368 (1986).See also Ronald Dworkin, Life’s Dominion 26 (1994) (“This more difficult issue requires us to decide the broader question of whether the Constitution should be understood as a limited list of the particular individual rights that statesmen now dead thought important, or as a commitment to abstract ideals of political morality that each generation of citizens, lawyers, and judges must together explore and reinterpret”).

*37* See Sunstein, supra note 13, at 19-20.In this article Sunstein notes the following:

*38*[C]onstitutional law in America (and in many other nations as well) has many features of the common law process. In that process, no one sets down broad legal rules in advance. The meaning of the Constitution is not a product of antecedent rules. Instead, the rules emerge narrowly as judges decide individual cases. Governing principles come from the process of case-by-case adjudication, and sometimes they cannot be known in advance. It does seem clear that much of constitutional law in the United States comes not from the constitutional text itself, but from judge-made constitutional law, interpreting constitutional provisions. For this reason, the meaning of the document is not rigidly fixed when the document is written and ratified. Id. at 14.

*39* See Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 36, at 360, 388; see also Proceedings of the Forty-Seventh Annual Judicial Conference of the District of Columbia Circuit, 114 F.R.D. 419, 447 (1987) (statement of Lawrence H. Tribe, Professor of Law).

*40* The Supreme Court, in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U.S. 483 (1954), stated that segregation with the sanction of law tends to retard the educational and mental development of African-American children and to deprive them of some of the benefits they would receive in an integrated system. “Whatever may have been the extent of psychological knowledge at the time of Plessy v. Ferguson,” stated the Court, “this finding is amply supported by modern authority. Any language in Plessy v. Ferguson contrary to this finding is rejected.” Id. at 494-95. Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896), sustained a Louisiana law of 1890 that segregated railroad passengers by race. In challenging the law, Plessy alleged that he was “seven-eighths Caucasian and one-eighth African blood; that the mixture of colored blood was not discernable in him; and that he was entitled to every right [of] the white race.” Id. at 538. Dworkin acknowledges the importance of construing the framers’ declarations, which are certainly “part of the community’s political record.” Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 36, at 365. “But we noticed how sensitive this argument is to time,” adds Dworkin. Id. It could not be weaker than it is in the present context, when the declarations were made not just in different political circumstances but to and for an entirely different form of political life. It would be silly to take the opinions of those who first voted on the Fourteenth Amendment as reporting the public morality of the United States a century later, when the racial issue had been transformed in almost every way. It would also be perverse; it would deny that community the power to change its public sense of purpose, which means denying that it can have public purposes at all. Id.

*41* We are grateful for a discussion with Professor Laurence Tribe that further expanded this idea. E-Mail from Laurence Tribe, Professor of Law, Harvard Law School (October 12, 1999) (on file with the author). As Professor Tribe observed, “[T]he time may come when genetic engineering and the computer sciences have created creatures that fill the supposed gaps between [human and non-human apes], on the one hand, and between computers and people, on the other. Once the lines are blurred by the introduction of numerous intermediate points, courts will have to start rethinking what the lines are all about anyway.” Id.

*42*Peter Singer, Rethinking Life and Death 180 (1994).

*43-44* Peter Singer, Practical Ethics 86 (2nd ed. 1998).

*45* JOHN LOCKE, Essay on Human Understanding, Bk. II, ch. 9, ¶ 29 (1690), quoted by Singer, supra note 42, at 87.

*46* See Singer, supra note 42, at 87. *47* See Gary L. Francione, Personhood, Property and Legal Competence, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 252.

*48* See id. at 253 (arguing cogently that moral consideration should adhere at sentience, but observing that wherever we “draw the line” to include beings for this consideration, it is clear that non-human great apes are on the same side as humans: “it would be irrational to place some great apes on one side, and some on the other.”).

*49* Mark A. Krause, Biological Continuity and Great Ape Rights, 2 ANIMAL L. 171, 173 (1996).

*50* See Elizabeth Pennisi, Are Our Primate Cousins ‘Conscious’? New Tests for Animal Intelligence, 284 Science 2073 (1999) (explaining that in the 1950s, anthropologists drew a line between human and other apes at the use of tools; thus any ancient hominid associated with stone tools was automatically assigned to our genus, Homo). Jane Goodall’s observations revised this paradigm. See generally Goodall, supra note 34. Gloria Grow and Dawna Grow of the Fauna Foundation in Québec, Canada have recorded details of the daily uses to which chimpanzees at their sanctuary put tools, as well as their impressive dexterity. Telephone Interview with Gloria Grow, Co-Founder of the Fauna Foundation (April 10, 2000). Fourteen of the fifteen chimpanzees open their own bottle tops; one ties and unties shoelaces; and most have no difficulty using keys, locks and bolts. Id. Several are adept at tea-making and washing dishes and toys. Id. Annie, the eldest chimpanzee at Fauna, frequently uses the squeeze nozzle to adjust the flow and direct the spray of a water hose in order to clean and remove foreign objects from gutters. Id. A chimpanzee who was extremely antisocial upon her arrival at the sanctuary has demonstrated a talent for removing splinters from Gloria’s and Dawna’s hands. Pepper removes the splinters with great care, using her thumbs as humans would. Id.

*51* See S.T. Boysen and G.T. Himes, Current Issues and Emerging Theories in Animal Cognition, Ann. Rev. of Psychol., Jan. 1, 1999, at 683. See also, e.g., BMF Galdikas, Orang-utan tool-use in Tanjung Puting Reserve, Central Borneo (Kalimantan Tengah), 10 J. Hum. Evol. 19-33 (1982).

*52* See generally Goodall, supra note 34; see also R.W. Byrne & A. Whiten, Machiavellian Intelligence: Social Expertise and the Evolution of Intellect in Monkeys, Apes and Humans. (Oxford Univ. Press. 1991)

*53-54* See Boysen and Himes, supra note 50, at 683 (describing the research of D. Premack & G. Woodruff, Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 1 Behav. Brain Sci. 515-26 (1978)).

*55* Although it provides further evidence of a consciouness which deserves consideration for Lockean persnhood, this “sophisticated level” of mental activity is not necessarily a valid test for determining whether an individual should have rights. See Gary L. Francione, Personhood, Property and Legal Competence, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 253. Professor Gary L. Francione has argued that it is not necessary to have human characteristics to have the right not to be treated as a human resource. Personal Interview with Gary L. Francione (Philadelphia, January 8, 2001). In contrast to Singer, Francione argues that the cognitive states attributable to most humans should not be the standard that defines personhood. Id. Sentience, argues Professor Francione, is sufficient evidence of self awareness: To be sentient means that when I hold a lighter to you, you have a mind that prefers or wants or desires not to feel pain. If I am conscious of pain, then logically I am self-conscious, because I know that it is I who am feeling the pain and not some third party. Id. For related discussion, see Gary L. Francione, Inroduction to Animal Rights 114-15, 140-41 (2000).

*56* See Boysen and Himes, supra note 50, at 683.

*57* Id. (citing GG Gallup, Jr., Chimpanzees: self-recognition. 167 Science 86-87 (1970)).

*58* Id. See also GG Gallup, Jr., Self-awareness and the emergence of mind in primates, 2 Am. J. Primatol. 237-48 (1982); GG Gallup, Jr., Toward a comparative psychology of self-awareness: species limitations and cognitive consequences, in The Self: an Interdisciplinary Approach 121-35 (GR Goethals & J. Strauss, eds. (1991).

*59-61* See Elizabeth Pennisi, supra note 49.

*62-64* See Lauran Neergaard, Startling insights about apes and us: Quick-thinking bonobo suggests human mental traits not unique, The Toronto Star, May 24, 1998, at F8.

*65* Fauna Foundation Home Page, at http://www.faunafoundation.org/home.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*66-72* Telephone Interview with Gloria Grow, Co-Founder of the Fauna Foundation (April 10, 2000).

*73-77* See Boysen & Himes, supra note 50 (citing D. Premack & G. Woodruff, Chimpanzee problem-solving: a test for comprehension, 202(3) Science 532-35 (1978)).

*78* See Roger Fouts & Stephen Tukel Mills, Next of Kin: My Conversations with Chimpanzees (1997).

*79-83* Id., at 291.

*84* See Peter Singer, Practical Ethics, supra note 42, at 86.

*85-86* The 25 Most Intriguing People ’96, Binti-Jua: She Gave a Helping Hand to a Distant—Very Distant—Relation, People, Dec. 30, 1996, at 66.

*87* Anne Marie O’Neill, Mary Green, and Paul Cuadros, One Great Ape: Binti-Jua, A West African Gorilla, Flexes Her Maternal Muscles to Save a Little Boy’s Life, People, Sept. 2, 1996.

*88* The 25 Most Intriguing People ’96, Binti-Jua: She Gave a Helping Hand to a Distant—Very Distant—Relation, People, Dec. 30, 1996, at 66.

*89* See Sapontzis, supra note 3, at 36.

*90*Id. Sapontzis notes that morally-based actions on the part of non-humans, especially when such actions are associated with cognitive abilities, have been repeatedly unrecognized by scientists, who have been “complacently sure that animals were not aware and could not think.” Id. at 61. Sapontzis compares this attitude with “the complacent assurance of gentlemen from ancient Greece to Victorian England concerning the intellectual and moral inferiority of women and of the embarrassing blindness to which that assurance led otherwise perceptive men.” Id.

*91* Binti Jua: Returning the Favor, Bridging the Gap, Newletter of the Great Ape Project International, Mar. 1997, http://www.greatapeproject.org/newsletters/BtG1P5.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*92-97* Fouts & Mills, Next of Kin, supra note 78, at 44.

*98* This factor is therefore considered by Peter Singer in Practical Ethics, supra, note 42, at 86, although linguistic ability is not necessarily a valid test for determining whether an individual should have rights. As Patterson and Gordon point out, “[m]any human beings—including all infants, severely mentally impaired people and some educationally deprived deaf adults of normal intelligence—fail to meet the criteria for ‘having language’ according to any definition…[b]ut the existence of even basic language skills does provide further evidence of a consciouness which deserves consideration.” Francine Patterson & Wendy Gordon, The Case for the Personhood of Gorillas, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 61.

*99* See generally Sue Savage-Rumbaugh & Roger Lewin, Kanzi: The Ape at the Brink of the Human Mind (1994).

*100* For various descriptions and further references, see Roger S. Fouts & Deborah H. Fouts, Chimpanzees’ Use of Sign Language, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 28-41; Francine Patterson & Wendy Gordon, The Case for the Personhood of Gorillas, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 58-77; and H. Lyn White Miles, Language and the Orang-utan: The Old ‘Person’ of the Forest, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 42-57.

*101* See generally Sue Savage-Rumbaugh & Roger Lewin, supra note 99.

*102* See, e.g., Mark D. Bodamer et al., Functional Analysis of Chimpanzee (Pan troglodytes) Private Signing, in 9 Human Evolution 281-296 (1994); and Roger S. Fouts & Deborah H. Fouts, Chimpanzees’ Use of Sign Language, inThe Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 34.

*103* See Francine Patterson & Wendy Gordon, The Case for the Personhood of Gorillas, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 58-59.

*104-105* Id. at 58.

*106* Id. at 58; see also id. at 61 (for a chart that tracks the intelligence tests taken in 1975 and 1976, chronological age in months, mental age in months, and specific results).

*107-108* Id. at 64.

*109* Id., at 65.

*110* Id. at 58-59.

*111* Id. at 59.

*112* Id. at 58. See also Singer, supra note 41, at 175-176 (describing similar behavior in other non-human great apes).

*113* See Francine Patterson & Wendy Gordon, The Case for the Personhood of Gorillas, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 58.

*114* See The Great Ape Trial, Channel Four Television broadcast, December 27th, 1995, produced by Wall to Wall Television, 8-9 Spring Place, Kentish Town, London, http://www.greatapeproject.org/archives/gatrial.html. Goodall cites apes’ interests as they correspond to those that underlie human rights: the family bonds that last through life, a life-span of fifty to sixty years, the fact that there’s a long childhood dependency, as in our own species, the fact that learning plays a very important part in the acquisition of adult behaviour, co-operation, [and] true altruism, which we’ve observed in the wild.… Id. Great apes kiss, hold hands, slap each other on the back, and show aggression—much as humans do. Id. For a related discussion on the similarities of human and chimpanzee psychology, including mourning the death of mothers, see Roger Fouts, My Best Friend is a Chimp, Psychology Today, July 1, 2000, at 68.

*115* See generally Dale Peterson and Jane Goodall, Visions of Caliban (2000).

*116* See Vining, supra note 28, at 144.

*117-118* John Chipman Gray, The Nature and Sources of the Law 27 (Roland Gray ed., MacMillan 1921) (1909).

*119* The idea of a “corporate person” is by no means new to the law, but one commentator has observed recently that the recognition of “corporate personality” incorporates an unspoken “agreement no longer to ask difficult questions about the “essence” of personality.” David Graver, Personal Bodies: A Corporeal Theory of Corporate Personhood, 6 U. Chi. L. Sch. Roundtable 235, 239 (1999) (citation omitted). Nevertheless, the court has had to deal with the “essence” of corporate personality on a case by case basis, and has held that the corporate person does not have all the rights of a natural person. See, e.g., Bell v. United States, 417 U.S. 85 (1974) (holding that a corporation has no right against self-incrimination, that right being limited to natural persons); Hague v. Comm. For Indus. Org., 307 U.S. 496, 514 (1939) (holding that a corporation is not entitled to the benefits of the Privileges and Immunities Clause); Fed. Deposit Ins. Corp. v. Hulsey, 22 F.3d 1472, 1489 (10th Cir. 1994) (holding that a corporation is not entitled to damages for emotional distress because “it lacks the cognizant ability to experience emotions”).

*120* See Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307, 324 (1982).

*121* See Attachment following this Brief.

*122* What is the ‘Community of Equals’?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.1, http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000) (emphasis in original).

*123* See Romeo, 457 U.S. at 314 (1982). Substantive due process concerns involve the area of law surrounding the rights of “privacy and personhood.” Justice Louis Brandeis defined the constitutional right of privacy as “the right to be let alone,” calling it “the most comprehensive of rights.” Olmstead v. United States, 277 U.S. 438, 478 (1928) (Brandeis, J., dissenting opinion); see also Tribe, supra note 29, §15-1, at 1302. In Washington v. Harper, 494 U.S. 210 (1990), the United States Supreme Court addressed the issue of a prison inmate given anti-psychotic drugs by the state of Washington, finding that an inmate’s interest in avoiding involuntary administration of antipsychotic drugs was protected under the Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause. The Court stated that “forcible injection of medication into a nonconsenting person’s body represents a substantial interference with that person’s liberty.” Id.at 229. T.D. v. N.Y. State Office of Mental Health, 650 N.Y.S.2d 173, 186 (1996), recognized that the right to reject treatment with anti-psychotic medication is not absolute, and that in certain emergency situations, “such as where the individual presents an imminent danger to himself or those in immediate proximity to him, that right may yield to compelling State interests.” The Court stated, however, that State interests unrelated to the well being of the initial and others in immediate proximity do not outweigh the individual’s fundamental autonomy interest. Id.

*124*Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307 (1982). Justice Blackmun’s concurrence is even more properly aligned with world opinion on the matter, in the Declaration 2856 (XXVI): Declaration on the Rights of Mentally Retarded Persons is an indication. Art 1 of the Declaration states that “the mentally retarded person has …the same rights as other human beings.” Declaration on the Rights of Mentally Retarded Persons, G.A. Res 2856, U.N. GAOR, 26thSess., Supp. No. 29, U.N. Doc. A/8429 (1971). Art 2 asserts a right to “such education, training, rehabilitation and guidance as will enable [development of] ability and maximum potential.” Id.

*125* Romeo, 457 U.S. at 315 (quoting Ingraham v. Wright, 430 U.S. 651, 673 (1977)).

*126* See S.T. Boysen and G.T. Himes, Current Issues and Emerging Theories in Animal Cognition, Ann. Rev. of Psychol., Jan. 1, 1999, at 683.

*127* Christoph Anstötz, Profoundly Intellectually Disabled Humans and Apes: A Comparison, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 161-62.

*128* Id., at 165. In tests developed to measure the intelligence of human children, the abilities of non-human great apes have generally correlated with those of humans between two and three years old, with some skills of even older children. See H. Lyn White Miles, Language and the Orang-utan: The Old “Person” of the Forest, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 49.Such cognitive assessments are necessarily conservative, for they require non-human hominids to make sense of human meanings, in human settings. See Barbara Noske, Great Apes as Anthropological Subjects: Deconstructing Anthropomorphism, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 266.

*129* See Jane Goodall, Chimpanzees – Bridging the Gap, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 13. See also Christoph Anstötz, Profoundly Intellectually Disabled Humans and Apes: A Comparison,” in The Great Ape Project,supra note 1, at 164.

*130* Christoph Anstötz, Profoundly Intellectually Disabled Humans and Apes: A Comparison, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 164-65 (for an analysis of Goodall’s study).

*131-132* Id. at 165.

*133* See Jane Goodall, Chimpanzees – Bridging the Gap, The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 13 (discussing chimpanzee’s capacity for suffering); see also Jane Goodall, supra note 32, at 241 (describing non-human great apes as naturally sociable and extremely active).

*134* U.S. Const. amend. V, “No person shall be…deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law…” U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 1, “nor shall any state deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law….”

*135* Justice Harlan once explained, [T]radition is a living thing…[The] full scope of the liberty guaranteed by the Due Process Clause cannot be found in or limited by the precise terms of the specific guarantees elsewhere provided in the Constitution. This “liberty” is not a series of isolated points…It is a rational continuum which, broadly speaking, includes a freedom from all substantial arbitrary impositions and purposeless restraints…which also recognizes [that]…certain interests require particularly careful scrutiny of the state needs asserted to justify their abridgment. Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 542-543 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting).

*136* See Walter F. Murphy et al., American Constitutional Interpretation 892-893 (2d ed. 1995).

*137* Williamson v. Lee Optical Co., 348 U.S. 461, 466 (1955).

*138* See Murphy, supra note 136, at 892-893.

*139* Charles Darwin acknowledged that species distinctions are not truly boundaries but merely categories of convenience. Charles Darwin, Origin of Species 98 (1859). Darwin wrote, “It is immaterial for us whether a multitude of doubtful forms be called species or sub-species or varieties….The mere existence of individual variability and of some few well-marked varieties, though a necessary foundation of the work, helps us but little in understanding how species arise in nature.” Id. By 1872, Darwin had shown by detailed observations that the expression of emotions in nonhuman primates is closely analogous to that in human beings. See generally Charles Darwin, The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals (3d ed. 1998).

*140* “There is no natural category that includes chimpanzees, gorillas and orangutans but excludes humans.” Richard Dawkins, Gaps in the Mind, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 82; see also Fouts & Mills, supra note 78, at 51-57.

*141* See David Cantor, Items of Property, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 280-89. Hundreds of chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas, and orang-utans are used by the entertainment and advertising industries, kept on display at zoos, or sold to private owners. Id. at 280. About 2000 great apes, primarily chimpanzees, live in laboratory cages in at least seven biomedical research institutions in the United States. Id.

*142* See id. at 284 (for a detailed description of the conditions in laboratories, and cases of resultant psychosis and deaths of non-human hominids).

*143* See, e.g., Reed v. Reed 404 U.S. 71 (1971) (holding that an Idaho statute which provides that as between persons equally qualified to administer estates males must be preferred to females, was based solely on a discrimination prohibited by, and violative of, the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment).

*144* See Jay Katz, Health Law Symposium: Human Experimentation and Human Rights, 38 St. Louis U. L.J. 7, 15 (1993).

*145* See, e.g., T.D. v. N.Y. State Office of Mental Health, 650 N.Y.S.2d 173, 193 (1996). In T.D., the Supreme Court of New York took notice of the competition among players in the pharmaceutical industry to market new psychiatric drugs. Id. Justice Ross wrote, It is evident that, given the motivation to test these medications and quickly bring them to market, industry-sponsored studies, which will not rely on Federal funds and therefore will not be strictly subject to Federal guidelines and oversight, will proliferate. These developments serve to highlight the importance of safeguarding the rights of incapable adults and minors, who may be potential subjects of greater than minimal risk studies involving psychiatric medications, through constitutionally acceptable protocols and guidelines promulgated by the appropriate agency. Id. at 194.

*146* See McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U.S. 184, 192 (1964) (describing racial classifications as “constitutionally suspect” under Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 499, and subject to the “most rigid scrutiny,” under Korematsu v. United States, 323 U.S. 214, 216 (1944), and “in most circumstances irrelevant” to any constitutionally acceptable legislative purpose under Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U.S. 81, 100 (1943)); see also Graham v. Richardson, 403 U.S. 365, 374-75 (1971) (holding that provisions of Arizona and Pennsylvania welfare laws conditioning benefits on citizenship were violative of the Equal Protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment because “an alien as well as a citizen is a ‘person’ for equal protection purposes”).

*147* Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 454 (1985) (Stevens, J., concurring) (discussing the mistreatment of the mentally disabled).

*148* U.S. Const. amend. V. *149* U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 2.

*150* Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U.S. 497, 498 (1954).

*151* See Dworkin, Life’s Dominion, supra note 36, at 128. *152* U.S. Const. amend. XIV, § 2.

*153* See Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 216 (1982).

*154* See, e.g., Romer v. Evans, 517 U.S. 620, 623 (1996).

*155* Cleburne v. Cleburne Living Center, Inc., 473 U.S. 432, 466 (1985) (Marshall, J., concurring in part and dissenting in part). Justice Marshall invited the reader to contrast Plessy v. Ferguson, 163 U.S. 537 (1896) and Bradwell v. Illinois, 16 Wall. 130, 141 (1873) (Bradley, J., concurring), with Brown v. Bd. of Educ., 347 U.S. 483 (1954), and Reed v. Reed, 404 U.S. 71 (1971). Id.

*156* The Fifth and Fourteenth Amendments to the Constitution expressly protect life against any government action taken without due process. U.S. Const. amend. V (“No person shall be…deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law…”); U.S. Const. amend. XIV § 1 (“…nor shall any state deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law…”).

*157* The Supreme Court has decided that certain rights not specifically enumerated in the Constitution are still fundamental ones. See, e.g., Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1956). See also Laurence H. Tribe, Foreward: Toward a Model of Roles in the Due Process of Life and Law, 87 Harv. L. Rev. 1, 43 (1973). For a thorough analysis of substantive due process concerns involving the rights of privacy and personhood, see Tribe, supra note 29, ch. 15.

*158* The Supreme Court has required such a connection in, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peña, 115 S. Ct. 2097, 2114, 2117 (1995).

*159* See Murphy, supra note 136, at 892-93.

*160* Jon Cohen, Overhauling AIDS Research: Views from the Community, 271 Sci. 590 (1996).

*161* Tribe, supra note 29, §15-2, at 1306.

*162* See, e.g., 45 C.F.R. §§ 46.05-46.06 (requiring stricter standards for research involving no prospect for direct benefit to the research subject). *163* For example, according to the National Association of Crime Victim Compensation Boards, $248,717,660 was paid to crime victims by state compensation boards in 1997 alone. Statistics Bear out the Toll Crime Takes on Society, Sunday Patriot – News (Harrisburg, PA), Ap. 25, 1999, at A. When the cost of medical care, lost earnings, pain, suffering, and dimuntion of the qualtiy of life are all considered, it is estimated that the annual cost of violent crime in this country is $450,000,000,000. Id.

*164* See Geraldine Brooks, In Chimp Sell-Off, Military Finds It Has Monkey on Its Back, The Wall Street Journal, Dec. 30, 1997, at A1.

*165* See In Re T.A.C.P., 609 So. 2d 588 (Fla. 1992).

*166-167* Brooks, supra note 164, at A1.

*168-170* The Oath of Hippocrates, reprinted in Jay Katz, Experimentation with Human Beings 311 (1972). For a general discussion of this trend, see Michael J. Loscialpo, Nontherapeutic Human Research Experiments on Institutionalized Mentally Retarded Children: Civil Rights and Remedies, 23 New Eng. J. on Crim. and Civ. Confinement 139 (1997). For a specific example, see Gary Lee, Final Data Released on Tests Involving Radiation Exposure, The Washington Post, August 18, 1995, at A23 (reporting that the United States Department of Energy found that researchers used 16,000 children, men, and women in radiation experiments from World War II to the mid-1970s).

*171* See Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307, 321 (1982).

*172* See generally Loscialpo, supra note 170.

*173* Jay Katz, Health Law Symposium: Human Experimentation and Human Rights, supra note 144, at 8.

*174* ee, e.g., Mackey v. Procunier, 477 F.2d 877, 877-78 (9th Cir. 1973) (prisoners); Begay v. U.S., 768 F 2.d 1059 (9th Cir. 1985) (Native American uranium mine workers); Mink v. Univ. of Chicago, 460 F. Supp. 713 (N.D. Ill. 1978) (pregnant women); Burton v. Brooklyn Doctors Hosp., 452 N.Y.S.2d 875 (N.Y. App. Div. 1982) (infants); United States v. Stanley, 483 U.S. 669, 671 (1987) (members of armed forces); Claire Alida Milner, Gulf War Guinea Pigs: Is Informed Consent Optional During War? 13 J. contemp. Health L. & Pol’y 199 (members of the armed forces). For an account of involuntarily hospitalized adults and children at Office of Mental Health psychiatric facilities who were adjudicated mentally incapable of giving or withholding informed consent to experimentation, see T.D. v. N.Y. State Office of Mental Health, 650 N.Y.S.2d 173 (1996) (citing failure to adequately protect common-law privacy and Fourteenth Amendment due process rights of potential subjects).

*175* See Henry K. Beecher, Ethics and Clinical Research, 274 New Eng. J. Med. 1354 (1966).

*176* Scott Allen, Radiation Used on Retarded, Boston Globe, Dec. 26, 1993, at 1. The non-therapeutic experiments, performed on adolescent subjects whose I.Q.s ranged from 46 to 75, led to the doctoral thesis of a Massachusetts Institute of Technology faculty member. See Loscialpo, supra note 170, at 143. The Quaker Oats Company provided funding, and the United States Atomic Energy Commission (AEC, now the Department of Energy) provided the radioactive isotopes. Id. at 143-44. See also Associated Press, Radioactive Oatmeal Suit Settled for $1.85 Million, The Washington Post, Jan. 1, 1998, at A17 (“reporting that the group of former students who ate radioactive oatmeal as unwitting participants in a food experiment will share a $1.85 million settlement from Quaker Oats and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology”). In an unrelated Fernald experiment, researchers justified the administration of an extremely dangerous amount of radiation to one ten-year-old child on the grounds that he was severely retarded [sic] and terminally ill with Hurler-Hunter syndrome. A Report on the Use of Radioactive Materials in Human Subject Research That Involved Residents of State-Operated Facilities Within the Commonwealth of Massachusetts From 1943 Through 1973, Task Force on Human Subject Research, Department of Mental Retardation B18, B27(1994). The researchers requested permission from the AEC to inject fifty microcuries of Ca-45 into the “moribund gargoyle,” as the child was called in the report by Fernald’s superintendent. Nonterminally ill retarded children were given one microcurie. Id.

*177-178* Robert I. Field, Children as Research Subjects: Science, Ethics & Law (M. Grodin & L. Glantz, eds., 1994), 16 J. Legal Med. 311, 311 (1995) (book review). See generally David J. Rothman & Sheila M. Rothman, The Willowbrook Wars (1984); Paul R. Friedman, The Rights of Mentally Retarded Persons (1976).

*179* Paul R. Friedman, The Rights of Mentally Retarded Persons 65 (1976).

*180* See generally Nat’l Research Act, Pub. L. No. 93-348, 88 Stat. 342 (1974) (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. § 241 (1994)).

*181* See Robert J. Levine, Ethics and Regulation of Clinical Research 236 (1988).

*182* See Loscialpo, supra note 170, at 148. The DHHS was a separate agency from the DHEW until 1980.

*183* See 45 C.F.R. §§ 46.405-46.406 (1994) (elucidating the standards for children as vulnerable subjects; additionally in cases of “[r]esearch not involving greater than minimal risk” under § 46.404, “adequate provisions” must be made “for soliciting the assent of the children and permission of their parents or guardians,” as set forth in § 46.408). Under 45 C.F.R. § 46.407(a) and (b), research in pursuit of generalized knowledge, i.e., “[r]esearch not otherwise approvable which presents an opportunity to understand, prevent, or alleviate a serious problem affecting the health or welfare of children,” will be conducted or performed only if the research “presents a reasonable opportunity to further the understanding, prevention, or alleviation of a serious problem affecting the health or welfare of children; and the HHS Secretary,” after consultation with a panel of experts in pertinent disciplines and following opportunity for public review and comment, has determined that [t]he research presents a reasonable opportunity to further the understanding, prevention, or alleviation of a serious problem affecting the health or welfare of children; [t]he research will be conducted in accordance with sound ethical principles; and [a]dequate provisions are made for soliciting the assent of children and the permission of their parents or guardians. Id.

*184* See supra note 9.

*185* See Sapontzis, supra note 3, at 174-175 (providing a discussion of the philosophical basis underlying a sentient being’s interest in life).

*186* See Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390, 399-400 (stating that the liberties, such as those protected by the Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment, “may not be interfered with, under the guise of protecting the public interest, by legislative action which is arbitrary or without reasonable relation to some purpose within the competency of the state to effect”). Moreover, the Supreme Court has ruled that even though a governmental prupose is legitimate and substantial, that prupose cannot be pursued by means that broadly stifle fundamental personal liberties when the end can be more narrowly achieved. Kusper v. Pontikes, 414 U.S. 51, 59 (1973); Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U.S. 92, 102 n.8 (1972); Keyishian v. Bd. of Regents of Univ. of N.Y., 385 U.S. 589, 602 (1967); Elfbrandt v. Russell, 384 U.S. 11, 18-19 (1966); Aptheker v. Sec’y of State, 378 U.S. 500, 508 (1964); see also Miller v. Murphy, 143 Cal. App. 3d 337, 342-43 (1st Dist. 1983) (under strict scrutiny analysis of a legislative regulation, in order to by upheld, it is required that the law be shown “necessary, and not merely rationally related to, the accomplishment of a permissible and compelling interest” (citation omitted)).

*187* The “compelling interest” prong of strict scrutiny requires not only that a compelling government interest exist, but also that the conduct be a substantially effective means for advancing that interest: if the challenged government action makes only a remote or speculative contribution to achieving the government’s prupose, strict scrutiny is not satisfied. See, e.g., The Fla. Star v. B.J.F., 491 U.S. 524, 540 (1989) (holding that strict scrutiny was not satisfied in part because of “serious doubts whether Florida is, in fact, serving, with this statute, the significant interests”); Eu v. San Francisco County Democratic Cent. Comm., 489 U.S. 214, 226 (1989) (explaining that, in the particular case, the government failed to show how the government action advanced its asserted interest); McDaniel v. Paty, 435 U.S. 618, 628-29 (1978) (concluding that the alleged threat addressed by the statute under review (an infection of the political process by clerical participation) was speculative, as it did not have a historical record of occurrence, and was therefore insufficient to establish the act’s constitutionality under strict scrutiny).

*188* The General Assembly of the United Nations has defined torture as “any act by which severe pain or suffering, whether physical or mental, is intentionally inflicted by or at the instigation of a public official on a person for such purposes as obtaining from him or a third person information or confession, punishing him for an act he has committed or is suspected of having committed, or intimidating him or other persons.” See The Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture, General Assembly Resolution 3452, 30 U.N. GAOR Supp. (No. 34) 91, U.N.Doc. A/1034 (1975), art. I. The Declaration expressly prohibits any state from permitting or tolerating torture or other cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment. Id. at art. III. The Declaration directs each state to take effective measures to prevent torture and other cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment or punishment from being practised within its jurisdiction, and to “ensure that all acts of torture as defined in article I are offenses under its criminal law. The same shall apply in regard to acts which constitute participation in, complicity in, incitement to or an attempt to commit torture.” Id. at art. VII. Legislative history of United Nations organs underscore the view that nonconsensual biomedical experiments are torture. The United Nations Preparatory Committee on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court included biological experiments, unlawful deportation and confinement as sub-categories of “offences as wilful killing, torture or inhuman treatment.” See Preparatory Committee for International Criminal Court Concludes Session, M2 Presswire, Dec.18, 1997.

*189* See Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture, supra note 188, art. III. A jus cogens, or peremptory, norm is defined by article 53 of the Vienna Convention as “a norm accepted and recognized by the international community of States as a whole as a norm from which no derogation is permitted and which can be modified only by a subsequent norm of general international law having the same character.” Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, 1155 U.N.T.S. 331, T.S. No. 58 (1980), reprinted in 8 I.L.M. 679-713 (1969), entered into force Jan. 27, 1980, art. 53.

*190* Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture, supra note 188, art. III.

*191* See Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment of Punishment, Model Treaty on Extradition, G.A. Res. 45/116, U.N. GAOR, 45th Sess., Supp. No. 49A, U.N. Doc. A/45/49 (1991). The international consensus surrounding torture has found expression in numerous international treaties and accords. See, e.g., The American Convention on Human Rights, art. 5, OAS Treaty Series No. 36 at 1, OAS Off. Rec. OEA/Ser 4 v/II 23, doc. 21, rev. 2 (English ed., 1975) (“No one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading punishment or treatment”); International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, U.N. General Assembly Res. 2200 (XXI)A, U.N. Doc. A/6316 (Dec. 16, 1966) (identical language); European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms, art. 3, Council of Europe, European Treaty Series No. 5 (1968), 213 U.N.T.S. 211 (semble ). Because Evelyn’s personhood places her within the curtilage of humanity for the purposes of these fundamental rights, petitioner invokes such conventions before this Court.

*192* That such plans fit the definition of torture is clear upon consideration of life in the laboratory. The history of Jean, an actual laboratory chimpanzee, is typical. Pharmaceutical giant Merck, Sharp & Dohme donated Jean (CH-562) to the Buckshire Corporation in 1981, when she was six years old. In 1988 she arrived at the Laboratory for Experimental Medicine and Surgery in Primates (LEMSIP), at New York University. There, she was continually given vaginal washes and cervical biopsies, and often reported to have self-inflicted wounds. In 1993 she was inoculated with HIV. Following a subsequent study in 1995, Jean suffered a nervous breakdown. She was heavily medicated for the next two years; yet throughout this time she experienced a series of aggressive seizures during which she removed her own fingernails, screamed incessantly, and thrashed out at anyone who came near her. In 1997 LEMSIP shut down and most of its non-human residents were shipped to Frederick Coulston’s laboratory in New Mexico for further invasive research. Jean, along with fourteen of her lab mates, was released to a private sanctuary at the insistence of Gloria Grow of the Fauna Foundation, who built a spacious indoor and outdoor facility to house as many chimpanzees as village zoning rules would allow. To this day, Jean suffers from “phantom hand” syndrome, a disorder that causes her to fight off her own hand as though it were attacking her. See Carlos Soldevila, Reuters News Service, Carignan, Québec (July 16, 1998, “A dozen chimpanzees used for biomedical research went out recently for a breather.”

*193* See Goodall, supra note 133 (discussing non-human great apes’ capacity for suffering).

*194* See, e.g., Attorney Gen. of N.Y. v. Soto-Lopez, 476 U.S. 898, 909-10 (1986) (“[If] there are other, reasonable ways to achieve [a compelling state purpose] with a lesser burden on constitutionally protected activity, a State may not choose the way of greater interference. If it acts at all, it must choose ‘less drastic means’” (citation omitted)).

*195* See Tribe, supra note 29, § 15-9, at 1334-35. Professor Tribe discusses the reciprocity requirement in physical intrusions, noting that such a requirement “serves to minimize the danger that a bodily invasion will be justified solely on the bais that the greater good of the society is served thereby; that one person’s two good eyes, distributed to two blind neighbors, might yield a net increase in happiness on the theory that one blind person will experience less misery than two, cannot justify a governmental decision to compel the exchange.” Id.

*196* The Declaration on the Protection of All Persons from Being Subjected to Torture, General Assembly Resolution 3452, 30 U.N. GAOR Supp. (No. 34) 91, U.N.Doc. A/1034 (1975).

*197* Louis Henkin, U.S. Ratification of Human Rights Conventions: The Ghost of Senator Bricker, 89 Am. J. Int’l. L. 341, 347-48 (1995) In 1988 President Reagan sought Senate consent to United States ratification of the Convention against Torture with reservations, and with a declaration that it shall not be self-executing. The executive branch apparently decided that the Convention should not be ratified until Congress enacted implementing criminal legislation required by the Convention. Congress finally enacted such legislation in April 1994 and the United States ratified the Torture Convention in October 1994. Id.

*198* Theodor Meron, On A Hierarchy of International Human Rights, 80 Am. J. Int’l L. 1, 11 (1986). Meron explains that the prohibition against torture is a fundamental right, observing its status as a non-derogable right under the American Convention on Human Rights, Nov. 22, 1969, 1144 U.N.T.S. 123, 9 I.L.M. 673, art. 4(1).

*199* See Filartiga v. Peña-Irala, 630 F.2d 876, 882. (2nd Cir. 1980). Stating that “there are few, if any, issues in international law today on which opinion seems to be so united as the limitations on a state’s power to torture persons held in its custody,” id. at 881, the Filartiga court found the prohibition against torture to be a basic principle of customary international law: “The treaties and accords… as well as the express foreign policy of our government, all make it clear that international law confers fundamental rights upon all people vis-à-vis their own governments…[W]e hold that the right to be free form torture is now among them.” Id. at 885.

*200* The Constitution states, states: [t]his Constitution, and the Laws of the United States which shall be made in Pursuance thereof; and all Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the Authority of the United States, shall be the supreme Law of the Land; and the Judges in every State shall be bound thereby, any Thing in the Constitution or Laws of any State to the Contrary notwithstanding. U.S. Const. art. VI, § 2, cl. 2 (emphasis added). See generally Kathryn Burke, et al., Application of International Human Rights Law in State and Federal Courts, 18 Tex. Int’l L.J. 291 (1983).

*201* See U.S. Const. art. VI, § 2, cl. 2. See also Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, 1155 U.N.T.S. 331, T.S. No. 58 (1980), reprinted in 8 I.L.M. 679-713 (1969), entered into force Jan. 27, 1980, art. 2. Treaties prevail over conflicting state law. Missouri v. Holland, 252 U.S. 416, 432 (1920). A treaty is ratified when the President signs it on the Advice and Consent of two-thirds of the United States Senate. U.S. Const. art. II, § 2, cl. 2.

*202* The U.S. has also ratified the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), G.A. Res. 2200A (XXI), U.N. GAOR, 21st Sess., Supp. No. 16, at 52, U.N. Doc. A/6316 (1966), 999 U.N.T.S. 171, entered into force Mar. 23, 1976, reprinted in 6 I.L.M. 368 (1967), adopted by the United States Sept. 8, 1992.

*203* U.S. Const. amend. VIII prohibits “cruel and unusual punishment.”

*204* 136 U.S. 436, 447 (1890).

*205* 217 U.S. 349, 378 (1910). Justice McKenna’s majority opinion stated that “[t]ime works changes, brings into existence new conditions and purposes. Therefore a principle to be vital must be capable of wider application than the mischief which gave it birth.” Id. at 373.

*206* Estelle v. Gamble, 429 U.S. 97, 106 (1976).

*207* 356 U.S. 86 (deeming §401(g) of the Nationality Act of 1940 unconstitutional). *208* Id. at 100-01.

*209* See Tribe, supra note 29, §15-9, at 1332.

*210* Mackey v. Procunier, 477 F.2d 877 (9th Cir. 1973).

*211* In the words of Justice Powell, “if it is cruel and unusual punishment to hold convicted criminals in unsafe conditions, it must be unconstitutional to confine the involuntarily committed—who may not be punished at all—in unsafe conditions.” Youngberg v. Romeo, 457 U.S. 307, 316 (1982).

*212* 27 U.S. (2 Pet.) 253, 314-15 (1829).

*213* See Jordan J. Paust, Self-Executing Treaties, 82 Am. J. Intl. L. 760, 782 (1988) (concluding that all treaties are presumptively self-executing, but excepting those which, by their terms considered in context, require domestic implementing legislation or seek to declare war on behalf of the United States: “All treaties are supreme federal law, but some treaties, by their terms, are not directly operative.”)

*214* Foster, 27 U.S at 314-15 (where Chief Justice Marshall analogized such a treaty to a contract that awaited congressional “execution”).

*215* Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States § 111 cmt. h (1987). The intent of the United States determines whether an agreement is to be self- executing in the United States or should await implementation by legislation or appropriate executive or administrative action. Id. Persuasive evidence of U.S. intent includes “any statement by the President in concluding the agreement or in submitting it to the Senate for consent or to the Congress as a whole for approval, and of any expression by the Senate or by Congress in dealing with the agreement.” Id.

*216* See, e.g., Richard Lillich & Frank Newman, International Human Rights: Problems of Law and Policy 71 (1979) (“At a minimum, [the Supremacy Clause] means that treaty obligations are automatically incorporated into U.S. domestic law, a situation that contrasts with that of most other domestic legal systems”).

*217* Advisory Opinion on the Legal Consequences for States of the Continued Presence of South Africa in Namibia (South West Africa), 1971 I.C.J. 16, 57.

*218* 242 P.2d 617 (Cal. 1952).

*219* Id. at 621-22. For a critique of the Sei Fujii decision, and the failure of federal courts to accommodate international law, most notably the United Nations Charter and the Universal Declaration, see Richard B. Lillich, The Role of Domestic Courts in Promoting International Human Rights Norms, in International Human Rights Law and Practice: The Roles of the United Nations, the Private Sector, the Government and Their Lawyers, 105, 130-31 (James C. Tuttle, ed., 1978). See also Virginia Leary, When Does the Implementation of International Human Rights Constitute Interference Into the Essentially Domestic Affairs of a State?, in International Human Rights Law and Practice,supra, at 15, 21. Leary concludes that “gross violations of human rights can no longer be considered a matter essentially within the domestic jurisdiction of the offending state under the U.N. Charter, although there are limitations on the permissible actions of the U.N. in response to such violations in the absence of the finding of a direct threat to international peace.” Id.

*220* See People v. Mirmirani, 636 P.2d 1130, 1138 n.1 (Cal. 1981) (Newman J., concurring); see also F. Newman & D. Weissbrodt, International Human Rights: Law, Policy and Process 294 (1990) (citing Frank Newman, Interpreting the Human Rights Clauses of the U.N. Charter, 1972 Revue des Droits de l’Homme 283). Newman and Weissbrodt argue that the International Bill of Human Rights provides the authoritative interpretation of the more vague language of articles 55 and 56 of the United Nations Charter. Id. at 582. The greater specificity that the International Bill of Human Rights offers therefore rebuts any suggestion that its provisions may be considered non-self-executing due to vagueness. Id. This position is known as the Newman-Berkeley thesis. Id. at 582 n.14.

*221* Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 189, at art. 2(1)(d), and art. 19.

*222* Art. 4(2) of International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (“ICCPR”), supra note 191, stipulates that State parties may not derogate from article 7: “[N]o derogation from articles 6, 7, 8 (paragraphs 1 and 2), 11, 15, 16 and 18 may be made under this provision.”

*223* See Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 189 at art. 53 (defining a peremptory norm as a norm from which no derogation is permitted); see also Nadine Strossen, Recent U.S. and International Judicial Protection of Individual Rights: A Comparative Legal Process Analysis and Proposed Synthesis, 41 Hastings L.J. 805, 816 (1990) (defining customary norms as “those that are so widely accepted by the international community that they are binding even on states that have not ratified treaties embodying them”).

*224* Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 189, at art. 53.

*225* See Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States § 102 reporter’s n.6 (1987); see also David Heffernan, America the Cruel and Unusual? An Analysis of the Eighth Amendment Under International Law, 45 Cath. U. L. Rev. 481 (1996). *226* 48 Revue Internationale de Droit Penal Nos. 3 & 4 at 208 (1977).

*227* See U.S. Const. amend. VIII (“Excessive bail shall not be required, nor excessive fines imposed, nor cruel and unusual punishments inflicted”).

*228* As stated by Chief Justice Marshall in The Nereide, 13 U.S. (9 Cranch) 388, 423 (1815), in the absence of a congressional enactment, United States courts are “bound by the law of nations, which is a part of the law of the land.”

*229* See Elizabeth Anderson, Value in Ethics and Economics 71 (1993).

*230* U.S. Const. amend. XIII, § 1.

*231* See The Civil Rights Cases, 109 U.S. 3, 33 (Harlan, J., dissenting).

*232* United States v. Rhodes, 27 F. Cas. 785, 788 (D. Ky. 1866).

*233* Hall v. Sims, District Court, 35 F. 152 (1888).

*234-235* Id. at 152-53.

*236* Id. at 154.

*237* See People for the Ethical Treatment of Animals v. Bobby Berosini, Ltd., 895 P.2d 1269, 1271 (Nev. 1995).

*238-239* Id. at 1272-73.

*240* Id. Similar accounts are available in the context of the circus industry. See, e.g., Helen Johnstone, Chipperfield Admits She was Wrong to Whip Chimp, The Times (London), Home News, Feb. 8, 1999 (describing circus trainer Mary Chipperfield’s conviction for twelve counts of cruelty to an 18- month-old chimpanzee who was kicked and whipped and spent fifteen hours out of twenty-four in a darkened box).

*241* See George Christie & Patrick Martin, Jurisprudence 90 (2d ed. 1995).

*242* Aristotle, Animals are for Our Use, reprinted in Political Theory and Animal Rights 57 (Paul A.B. Clarke & Andrew Linzey eds., 1990).

*243* Id. at 56-57.

*244* Geza Teleki, They Are Us, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 301.

*245* Id.

*246* Two investigators, posing as buyers, were offered five chimpanzees in one day in the markets of Istanbul. See Gareth Jenkins, Baby Chimps Starve in Booming Turkish Trade, The Sunday Times (London), July 5, 1998, at 20.

*247* Robert Liston, Slavery in America 32 (1970).

*248* John Henrik Clarke, Introduction to Tom Feelings, Middle Passage: White Ships/Black Cargo (1995).

*249* Liston, supra note 247, at 35-36.

*250* The term “chattel” symbolizes the parallel between the institution of human slavery and the exploitation between species; the word “cattle” is derived from “chattel.” See Paola Cavalieri & Peter Singer, The Great Ape Project – and Beyond, in The Great Ape Project, supra note 1, at 304.

*251-253* Daggs v. Frazer, 6 F.Cas. 1112 (D. Iowa. 1849).

*254* Thomas D. Russell, Articles Sell Best Singly: The Disruption of Slave Families at Court Sales, 1996 Utah L. Rev. 1161, 1162 (1996).

*255* See Tessa M. Gorman, Back on the Chain Gang: Why the Eighth Amendment and the History of Slavery Proscribe the Resurgence of Chain Gangs, 85 Calif. L. Rev. 447 (1997).

*256* 7 Statutes of South Carolina, at 359-60 (Act of 1696, ch. 314). Barbara L. Bernier noted that castration was deemed a medical procedure, and state laws throughout the south permitted it to be performed by slaveholders. Barbara L. Bernier, Class, Race, and Poverty: Medical Technologies and Sociopolitical Choices, 11 Harv. Blackletter L. J. 115, 121 (1994). Bernier refers to Winthrop D. Jordan, White Over Black: American Attitudes Toward the Negro, 1550-1812, 154, 156 (1968), which explains the common practice as stemming from the perception of slaves as chattel to be controlled by their owners, and a method of both punishment and sexual control.

*257* William W. Hening, The Statutes at Large: Being a Collection of All the Laws of Virginia, From the First Session of the Legislature in the Year 1619 (1823) 481 (Act of 1680, ch. 10).

*258-260* Kenneth Scott, The Slave Insurrection in New York in 1712, 45 N.Y. Hist. Soc’y Q. 43, 62 (1961).

*261* See William M. Wiecek, Part I: The Origins of the Law of Slavery in British North America, 17 Cardozo L. Rev. 1711, 1733 (1996).

*262* Id. at 1734; see also Arthur O. Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being: A Study of The History of an Idea (1936).

*263* Id.

*264* Winthrop D. Jordan, White over Black: American Attitudes Toward the Negro, 1550-1812 228 (1968).

*265* Id. at 218-21 (examining Linnaeus’s 1758 work Systema Naturae).

*266* Id. at 220-21.

*267* See Thomas Gossett, Race: The History of an Idea in America 69-70 (1997).

*268* William M. Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1734-35 (quoting David Hume, Of National Characters (1753-54 ed.), in Essays Moral, Political, and Literary (1898)). Similarly, Dr. Samuel Morton in Crania Americana stated that skulls from different races consistently differed from ancient times. Morton expounded the idea of race as a separate species. See D. Marvin Jones, Darkness Made Visible: Law, Metaphor, and the Racial Self, 82 Geo. L. J. 437, 481 n.178 (1993).

*269* See, e.g., J. A. C. Thomas, The Institutes of Justinian: Text, Translation and Commentary 6 (Book I, Tit. II) (1975) (“long-practised customs endorsed by the acquiescence of those who observe them take on the mantle of law”).

*270* See The Slave, Grace, 2 Hag. 94 (1827) (stating that “ancient custom is generally recognised [sic] as a just foundation of all law”).

*271* See The Antelope, 23 U.S. (10 Wheat) 66, 115 (1825) (noting that the slave trade, and a fortiori slavery itself, “has claimed all the sanction which could be derived from long usage, and general acquiescence”).

*272* See Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1775.

*273* See generally The Antelope, 23 U.S. (10 Wheat.) 66 (1825).

*274* Regarding the influence of Barbados on mainland slave codes, see M. Eugene Sirmans, The Legal Status of the Slave in South Carolina, 1660-1740, 28 J. S. Hist. 462, 462-73 (1962). Beginning with the premise that Africans were “brutish,” the Barbadian 1661 slave code imposed a violent police regime. Id.; see also Richard S. Dunn, Sugar and Slaves: The Rise of the Planter Class in the English West Indies, 1624-1713 283-342 (1972).

*275* See A. Leon Higginbotham, Jr., In the Matter of Color, 189 (1978) Gradually, the legislature began to realize that slaves were subjected to brutal acts by their masters, whether in the form of physical injury or failure to provide adequate provisions, and the legislature then made some efforts to protect the slaves. The tension between the master’s absolute right to control his slave and a societal concern for the minimum well-being of slaves and for maintaining a viable slave system becomes apparent. However, the statutes were devoid of any enforcement power to protect the slave from his master’s abuses. Id.

*276* See Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1778-79.

*277* See id. at 1779.

*278* See id. at 1743, (citing Article 91, The Laws and Liberties of Massachusetts 4 (Max Farrand ed., 1929)).

*279* Leviticus 25:46.

*280* Leviticus 25:44.

*281* Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1741-42 (quoting Simeon E. Baldwin, Theophilus Eaton, First Governor of the Colony of New Haven, in 7 New Haven Colony Hist. Soc’y Papers 11 (1908)).

*282* See Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1753.

*283-284* Id., at 1754.

*285* See generally Reports of Cases Determined in the General Court of Virginia (Thomas Jefferson ed., 1829) (reporting forty-two cases, twenty-three of which involve slavery).

*286* See Letter from Emanuel Downing to John Winthrop, 1745, in Documents Illustrative of the History of the Slave Trade to America 7 (Elizabeth Donnan ed.).

*287* See T.H. Breen, A Changing Labor Force and Race Relations in Virginia 1660- 1710, 7 J. Soc. Hist.J 3, 18 (1973) (stating that, despite the possibility for a few decades “to overlook racial differences, a time when a common experience of desperate poverty and broken dreams brought some whites and blacks together,” “[b]y 1700, whites had achieved a sense of race solidarity at the expense of blacks. Negroes were set apart as objects of contempt and ridicule. The whites, even the meanest among them, always knew there was a class of men permanently below them”).

*288* Wiecek, supra note 261, at 1713.

*289* Dred Scott v. Sandford, 60 U.S. 393, 404-05 (1856).

*290-291* Id. at 407.

*292* Contrast Frontiero v. Richardson, 411 U.S. 677 (1973) with Muller v. Oregon, 208 U.S. 412 (1908).

*293* See Barbara L. Bernier, supra note 256, at 120.

*294*Todd L. Savitt, Medicine and Slavery: Diseases and Health Care of Blacks in Antebellum Virginia 293 (1978).

*295* Barbara L. Bernier, supra note 256, at 118-119.

*296* Id. at 119.

*297* Id. at 120 (explaining that, “[a]s a result of Jefferson’s efforts, vaccinations became an established procedure in Virginia and ultimately throughout the United States”).

*298* Id. at 119-120.

*299* T.D. v. N.Y. State Office of Mental Health, 650 N.Y.S.2d 173, 177 (1996).

*300* Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire, supra note 36, at 390.

*301* See, e.g., Prepared Statement of Richard Lattis, Senior Vice President and General Director, Zoos and Aquarium Wildlife Conservation Society [and] President, American Zoo and Aquarium Association, Before the House Committee on Resources Subcommittee on Fisheries Conservation, Wildlife and Oceans, Federal News Service, June 20, 2000. Testifying on H.R. 4320—the Great Ape Conservation Act—Richard Lattis stated that the American Zoo and Aquarium Association [AZA] mission is “to support membership excellence in conservation, education, science and recreation.” Id. Collectively, AZA institutions “teach more than 12 million people each year in living classrooms, dedicate over $50 million annually to education programs that focus on, among other things, the devastating effects of the loss of vital species habitat and the illegal trade in endangered species parts and products, invest over $50 million annually in scientific research and support over 700 field conservation and research projects in 80 countries.” Id. Lattis also stated, “AZA member institutions have established the Species Survival Plan (SSP) program- longterm plan involving genetically-diverse breeding, habitat preservation, public education, field conservation and supportive research to ensure survival for many threatened and endangered species, including all the great apes—chimpanzees, gorillas, orangutans and bonobos (a.k.a., pygmy chimpanzees).” Id.

*302* Id. (testifying that “the AZA Ape Advisory Group scientifically manages apes in zoological environments and promotes primate conservation in the wild.”)

*303* See What is the Great Ape Project’s policy on sanctuaries for non-human great apes?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.2 http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*304* See generally Gary L. Bostwick, Comment, Taxonomy of Privacy: Repose, Sanctuary, and Intimate Decision, 64 Cal. L. Rev. 1447 (1976). Repose refers to privacy as (i) freedom from unwanted stimulii; (ii)sanctuary, which is protection against intrusive observation; and (iii) intimate decision, which is the autonomous making of life choices. Id. The importance of the interest in sanctuary can be brought into sharp focus when we consider the now-famous Mende group, captives from the mutineered ship “Amistad.” Although they were not made slaves, the group’s members lived in a New Haven jail for two years, ostensibly for their own safety. Jean Thompson, Where the Walls Speak, The Baltimore Sun, Mar. 1, 1998, at 1R. There, they were tutored in English speech and etiquette, and examined by phrenologists, who believed that the shape of one’s head revealed intellect and personality. Id. Plaster casts were made of their heads, followed by wax figures designed for a travelling exhibit. Id. The jailer, meanwhile, collected 12½ cents from thousands of tourists who came to have a look at the captives. Id. The U.S. District Court declared them free in January 1841, a decision upheld by Supreme Court in March of the same year. Id.; see also Jean Thompson, Tracing the Steps of Amistad Survivors, The Baltimore Sun, Mar. 1, 1998, at 1R (describing the Mende group’s subsequently restricted lives in Connecticut, where slavery continued until 1848).

*305* See What is the Great Ape Project’s policy on great apes kept in zoos?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.3 http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*306* See What is the Great Ape Project’s policy on sanctuaries for non-human great apes?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.2, http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*307* The Great Ape Project defines a sanctuary as an institution where the needs, interests and rights of the apes come first, and where the facilities, long-term financing, expertise and resources necessary to satisfy those needs, interests and rights are provided. See id.

*308* 457 U.S. 307, 314 (1982).

*309* See Prepared Statement of Richard Lattis, supra note 301. Lattis called the severe endangerment of non-human hominids’ lives “an ecological and societal problem of enormous proportions. Id. It is a problem of political unrest compounded by unregulated resource exploitation through logging, mining, farming and poaching. It is also a problem which is not specifically limited to the African continent as similar situations have arisen in Brazil, Sumatra, and Borneo, where the orangutan population has declined by 90%. Id.

*310* John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 141 (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971); see also Sapontzis, supra note 3, at 108 (for a similar analysis with respect to relations among species).

*311* The Declaration on Great Apes was first published in The Great Ape Project: Equality Beyond Humanity (Paola Cavalieri & Peter Singer eds., 1994). See What is the ‘Community of Equals’?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.1, http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000). The long-term goals of the Declaration supporters are: (1) a United Nations Declaration of the Rights of Great Apes; and (2) the designation of guarded territories to enable chimpanzees, bonobos, gorillas, and orang-utans to live freely in their own ways. See What is the Great Ape Project?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 1.1, http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000).

*312* In arguing for this right, The Great Ape Project does not advocate throwing the gates open at every zoo. See What is the Great Ape Project’s policy on great apes kept in zoos?, The Great Ape Project – GAP FAQ, Section 3: Principles and Policies, 3.3, http://www.greatapeproject.org/gapfaq.html (last visited Nov. 17, 2000). The overarching concern is that liberty not be denied for the purpose of human gratification. Id. The concerns of the individual in confinement are considered paramount. Id. A sanctuary conducive to future safety, designed in such a way that privacy and autonomy are maximized, may be the best possible life for great apes who could not be expected to revert successfully to survival in the wild. Id. Recognition of the liberty interest would mean that in the future, non-human hominids would not be captured or bred for human purposes of experimentation, entertainment, or public display. Thus, if non-human hominids can voluntarily place themselves in view of the public, there should be a sign clearly saying that these are the last generation of great apes in zoo captivity. See id.


Banner photo: William H. Calvin, “A female chimpanzee at Twycross Zoo UK” (2005); link to licensing: CC BY-SA 4.0 Int’l.

If You Can’t Stand the Heat, Get ANIMAL PRODUCTS Out of the Kitchen

That’s the topic of a presentation I’ll offer on 9 September 2017.

Hurricane Harvey’s unfolding tragedy is connected to climate change—which is, in turn, connected to animal agribusiness in a very big way. Equipped with the facts, let’s encourage people to stop eating like there’s no tomorrow or they could be right.

Is veganism really about climate, though?

Yes, squarely. Without a well-functioning atmosphere, advocating for habitat preservation and animal liberation is spitting into the wind. Climate crisis is an urgent subject for everyone to discuss, but this “inconvenient truth” has never been adequately addressed by policy devoid of a vegan perspective.

This presentation will take place at the 3rd annual Vegstock Festival, which is now seeking . . .

Activists · Artists · Authors · Doctors · Dietitians · Musicians Cooks · Chefs · Farmers · Foodies · Gardeners · Growers · Healers · Thinkers · Speakers · Students & Teachers for the Vegstock Vegan Festival. And folks to spread the word.



Presented by Wildflower Vegan Cafe, the vegan restaurant in Millville, NJ and the Millville Development Corporation. Time and place: 10am-4pm Saturday, September 9 2017. 501 North High Street, Glasstown Arts District, Millville NJ 08332.

“If You Can’t Stand the Heat, Get Animal Products Out of the Kitchen” is made possible by dedicated patrons of the Art of Animal Liberation.

Cuteness and Memes in Wildflower Cafe Slideshow

Start Your World Vegan Month at Wildflower Vegan Cafe

What’s Up? Enjoy cake and a cup of fair-trade coffee or a hearty vegan meal at Wildflower on the first Saturday in November, when I’ll facilitate a slideshow and conversation on Cuteness and Memes in Animal Advocacy.

Where? Wildflower Vegan Cafe, Village on High, Millville, NJ.  856.265.7955

When? 4 pm on Saturday 5 November 2016

We’ve all seen “Why love one but eat the other” images. Indeed, why do we love a puppy yet have no regrets when it comes to eating the calf? Then again…

Does setting the ideal in “loving” animals compromise nonhuman dignity? What can other social movements teach us about these idealized images?

Eric Nyman, owner of Wildflower Vegan Café, said, “Our business is nurturing bodies and minds. We’re excited to open November, which has traditionally been World Vegan Month, by offering space for Lee’s work on memes—inviting advocates and the public to consider how feel-good imagery might endorse exploitation.”

Event sponsored by Wildflower Vegan Café, and patrons of the art of animal liberation.

A Performance Review of Humanity

On Earth Overshoot Day, which inches earlier each year, we exhaust more resources than Earth annually regenerates. #Pledgefortheplanet, we tweet! But what of the root-level change needed to address “over-exploitation” of Earth and its living communities?

Throughout our range across the Earth’s surface, we deem ourselves nature’s managers. Managers usually have to account for themselves in performance reviews. What if Earth Overshoot Day prompted a performance review of humanity?

Let’s try it.


Essay by Bill Drelles, Lee Hall, and matt shaw. Banner photo by Mónica Vereau.

Michelle-Melania Plagiarism: Tempest in a Posh Teacup

This graduation season, Michelle Obama gave a commencement speech for the City University of New York. The country’s largest urban public university, CUNY is historically dedicated to bolstering opportunities for people of modest backgrounds. Michelle Obama’s speech, at CUNY’s flagship City College in the Harlem District of Manhattan, lauded this year’s graduates for their own struggles. But the bright-pink elephant in the room—City College reportedly makes higher-than-average use of both part-time and adjunct teaching staff—never got a mention.

. . .At this time, knowledge is critical to a public understanding of civilization-threatening problems. A 2014 Pew Research survey showed that most people who’ve attained a college degree know that global warming is driven by human activity, while most people without that education do not.

And if this is so, higher education matters urgently to sound politics.

But opportunities to contribute to society, its knowledge, and its policies are being denied to current and future teachers and researchers.

Meanwhile, people positioned to change this are speechifying at commencements.

Read this piece in full in today’s edition of CounterPunch.

New Book on Animal Liberation Now Available

ASIL OTOT AL

Cover of On Their Own Terms: Animal Liberation for the 21st Century

I’m pleased to report that On Their Own Terms: Animal Liberation for the 21st Century is now available.

Carolyn Bailey of AR Zone has called it “one of the most important books on animal activism for a long time” (cheers, Carolyn!) and I hope friends at Vegan Place will find it worth your valuable time.

Click on any direct link to find the book where you are: here for a link to the book on Amazon.com (U.S.); or here for Britain. In Canada; in Spain.

At this time it is only available on Kindle, but the good news is that a Kindle reader can be freely obtained from the sites linked above, to use on a regular computer, tablet, or phone. I hope to do a print edition later in the year.

Let me know what you think. Love & liberation,

Lee.

Coming Soon…New Book on Animal Liberation

Readers of VeganPlace and my fellow bloggers will, I hope, be excited to know that I’m making a debut as an “indie” by way of Kindle Direct Publishing. The new work, for which VeganPlace will become a discussion platform, is just days away from publication. This week, I’ll announce the Kindle link, price, and so forth. It might be free for the first five days, and in any case it will be under a tenner.

And COVER jpg fileI’d love for you to read it and review it. Writing a review will be the single most helpful thing you can do to support this work, beyond reading it. Keep in mind that this is a book by an indie vegan author, not an e-pub ninja; so don’t expect technical perfection on the first go. The e-publication phase has been much more difficult than I’d expected. The information technology-loving Cathy Burt has stepped up at the eleventh hour to work out a few glitches, although, given our time limitations, a paragon of production is not a reasonable goal. We’re learning as we go.

As for the substance, you might well ask what makes this new book worth your time. I believe the concept of animal liberation has never been more relevant, but…that concept is due for renovation. On Their Own Terms: Animal Liberation for the 21st Century updates the idea of animal liberation, as it explores the hits and misses of animal-rights and environmental advocacy, and presents a brief guide to the burgeoning vegan movement.

And why would I say a new animal-liberation philosophy is so important? Look at the way world leaders are now reacting to weather and climate dynamics. Finally they are reacting, but that’s basically to figure out how we can keep doing what we’ve been doing in supposedly “sustainable” ways. Until we redefine our role within Earth’s great biological community, the changes we find ourselves forced to accept will mean coping with one emergency after another.

Animal liberation should come to the fore during discussions of “sustainable” gatherings and products. Promoters of sustainable animal agribusiness or sustainable meals made with local vegetables and flesh of pigs, cows, or fish purchased from small farms or local waters don’t usually want to talk about animal liberation. It is important to meet these organizers where they are: to acknowledge their concern about a topic of great importance, and then to direct their attention to the question of whether their unspoken ethic of human dominion is sustainable.

On Their Own Terms: Animal Liberation for the 21st Century offers ways of uncovering our personal connections with the current climate and extinction crises. It explores the human potential to fit our own habitat, while allowing nonhuman communities to thrive in theirs.

Consider that a transformation of our human identity will spare us, and every other biological community on Earth, from enduring an endless string of gradually or abruptly worsening emergencies whose roots we fail to address. Consider, if you will, relinquishing the human assumption that the Earth is ours…


 

“I believe Lee Hall is one of the most interesting and insightful writers working in animal rights. This book gets all the thumbs-up.”

— Jonathan Hussain, rescuer and campaigner, Grass Valley, California

“In On Their Own Terms: Animal Liberation for the 21st Century, Lee Hall reclaims the concepts of animal liberation, animal rights and animal welfare, and compels us to reimagine what it means to be an animal activist.”

— Sangamithra Iyer, Satya Magazine

Veganism Defined

Veganism is a social movement. It’s based on the principle that human beings should live without exploiting animals.

Vegans seek to end the use of other animals for food, commodities, work, hunting, vivisection—and all exploitation of animal life.

In the hope of achieving the ideal, vegans commit to living as closely to it as personal circumstances permit.

Karen Pearlman - bee on sunflowerWhile veganism is not a diet, vegans do apply the principle to their diets, committing to complete and consistent vegetarianism.

People become vegetarians for various reasons—humanitarian, ecological, health-based, etc. Veganism, though, is a principle—that we have no right to dominate and control other animals—so we follow a consistent, animal-free diet. Free of flesh, whether of mammals, birds, or sea animals, free of eggs, free of honey, free of animal milk and its derivatives, our culinary arts are plant-based, wholesome, and guided by fairness. We seek animal liberation—that is, reintegration of other animals within the balance and sanity of nature itself.

Our purpose is to redeem a great mistake, with the stupendous effect it has had upon the Karen Pearlman - windblown sunflowercourse of evolution. As veganism spreads, the conception of other animals as existing within Earth’s great bio-community for us to possess will begin to fade away.

The purpose of veganism transcends welfare; its goal is liberation—of other animals and of the human spirit.

It is not so much an effort to make the present relationship between ourselves and other animals bearable, as an uncompromising recognition that because it is basically one of master and slave, that relationship has to be abolished before something better and finer can be created.


EXPLANATORY note: this work is not mine; It’s part of a collective exercise. I’m a member of The Vegan Society, and I subscribe to THE DEFINITION OF VEGANISM OFFERED by its foundING MEMBERS. take a look at VEGANISM DEFINED FOR THEIR FULL DEFINITION, POSTED COURTESY OF THE INTERNATIONAL VEGETARIAN UNION. I DOUBT I COULD improve upon That striking piece, nor do I need to. But, prompted by conversations with Will Anderson of GreenVegans.org, Harold, James and Jenny of HumaneMyth.org, and other thoughtful people at the 2015 North American Vegetarian Society’s Summerfest conference, I’ve given my 21st-century language a go in conveying the basics of the definition originally published in 1951. Appreciation to PHOTOGRAPHER and friend KAREN BETH PEARLMAN.

Factory Farming, Farm Sprawl, or a Genuine Humane Response?

Conversation with Caryn Hartglass

Caryn Hartglass has given reprint permission for this 2014 interview with me on the show It’s All About Food. This transcript is proofed and edited for Vegan Place. Original podcast and transcript, titled Animals, Environment, and the Law, appears on the REAL Radio site.

INTRO:

Lee Hall speaking on climate

Lee Hall, an author who’s taken on subjects from anti-terrorism law to vegan cooking, wrote the “Vegetarianism” entry in the Encyclopedia of Activism and Social Justice. Lee has taught Animal Law and Immigration and Refugee Law, and is today working on a second law degree—a legal masters in Environmental Law with a focus on climate change from Vermont Law School. Lee’s work is a bridge between environmentalism and our personal relationships with agriculture, confronting the way animal farming usurps habitat. For years, animal-rights advocates have operated under the belief that at least pasture-based or organic ranching represents a “step” in the humane direction—but only looking at how domesticated animals seem to be affected. Lee champions the animal communities displaced by farm sprawl, and explains how our chosen cookbooks can offer a genuine humane response for all animals, reduce greenhouse emissions, and even stop extinctions.

TRANSCRIPTION:

Lee Hall, Welcome to It’s All About Food.

Lee Hall: Thank you, Caryn. It seems to be perfect timing given that you’re the Lone Vegan ready to speak with two hundred cattle ranchers.

Caryn Hartglass: I know, I was hoping that you would give me some really good tips for Saturday.

Lee Hall:  I am imagining that we are going to have quite a good conversation given that we are both studying the same thing right now.

Caryn Hartglass: I know. And the first thing I wanted to ask you, I’ve been following you and your work for a long time and it’s incredible and the thing that I know about you is your intensity, your passion, how principled you are.

Lee Hall:  Thank you.

Caryn Hartglass: And I wondered were you born that way, or was there something that happened in your life that made that happen, or was it a slow process, or none of the above.

Lee Hall: Well, I wasn’t born that way. I actually saw a bullfight when I was a child and it didn’t change me. I look back on it—and maybe it did, ultimately. I look back on it and I think why didn’t that change me, witnessing a bullfight; I mean, the bull was killed. This was in Mexico. My parents worked there they got free tickets from a business associate. Right, so we went and saw the novicios, who are the people that are learning to do bullfights. Which I understand is more difficult to watch. I wouldn’t know; I’ve only seen this particular instance. And I was—I hid myself in the bathroom for over a day. I wouldn’t come out after it. And what I guess I thought was weirdest—as terrible as this was, as traumatic as it was to see and hear people standing up and cheering for the slow death of an animal, not to mention what the horses were going through in the ring—of all of the horrific feelings of this the very worst was that I was surrounded by hundreds of people that were cheering.

Caryn Hartglass:  Yeah.

Lee Hall: And so here I am locking myself in the bathroom and I remember trying to make a soap carving for hours and I heard my mother trying to get me out of the bathroom, saying “It’s all right, the meat, the flesh of the bull will go to the poor children of Mexico.” My mother knew I was very concerned about poverty; I did have a feeling of social justice as a little kid, as I think most little kids do. But, I think back and the tie: right there, my mother telling me. Of course that didn’t help me feel better that they were going to eat the bull. But: why didn’t I connect as a child? What didn’t I connect? And I know people who do they see an animal killed and immediately they put it all together.

Caryn Hartglass:  Most don’t.

Lee Hall: Most don’t. It takes—I  don’t know what happens. I don’t know how. If I knew how to make this all work, I would tell you. But, I was 21 and I met Robin Lane who is now the co-facilitator/founder of the London Vegan Festival, the longest running vegan festival anywhere in the world. It is the one that inspired all the vegan festivals to come. This was long before that had been started.

Robin Lane in London had been vegan for 1 year and met me. As far we know, I am Robin’s longest running protégé.  It was a leaflet. It was all the ways we use animals. And I considered myself a feminist—it was one of the areas I was reading about myself; and something just clicked then and there. It was: How can I think about oppression and want to get over oppression and want to transcend that in my life and get over that in my life and be working so hard mentally to transcend differences and hierarchies—and how have I not noticed this before? Then of course the bullfight came back to me. But, I just said, that will be it! So I’m one of the weird people that did decide to go vegan all at once.

Caryn Hartglass:  Yeah, for the weird people. Let’s hear it for socially peculiar. Yeah! Making the world a better place.

Lee Hall:  So that was 31 years ago.

Caryn Hartglass:  Yeah. Good for you. I just wonder, because I want to think that we all have the potential to not exploit to not cause pain and suffering; I want to believe that. And I want to believe that we are not born with one kind of DNA that makes us more compassionate then others. I want to think that we are all flexible and once the veil is lifted we can move on and do better.

Lee Hall: Well, I think that is true, Caryn. I was that person until I was 21 and I knew and I didn’t change. So look at other people as people who could change any day.  You have had Harold Brown on the show?

Caryn Hartglass: Yeah.

Lee Hall: That is a wonderful example. Harold came from a dairy and beef farming family and would have been a successful dairy and beef farmer today and had been doing that for many, many years, and a light bulb—this is also somebody that had been hunting regularly.

Caryn Hartglass:  Yes. You are in environmental law now. I want to talk more about animals and the environment. And one of the things we are hearing about is people that care about the environment and seem to have more compassion for animals. They want to go for the—quote—more humane ways of raising animals for food, pasture grazing; and I am doing my studying for this climate change talk. There is this guy on the panel that believes in animal agriculture intensification because unfortunately we have learned that animal agriculture intensification is—quote—more efficient and produces less greenhouse gases when you are cramming this animals in small space and feeding them the wrong foods. But nobody talks about the things that are wrong with it. But it’s encouraging this horror instead of the other way around. And let’s just talk about how all these other things affect the environment.

Lee Hall: Let’s talk about that. It’s a very interesting sort of squeeze that you bring up. You mentioned that the intensify of farming can be controlled in a way that it is less of an emitter of greenhouse gases, that it takes up less space environmentally, these kinds of things. That is a very significant point to bring up. I think a lot of advocates want to think that everything about factory farms is wrong and that’s the answer and we just say that. Just say factory farms. We are saying something that of course everyone understands. Of course it is all kinds of animal farms, the problem we are dealing with. It’s animal farming; it’s not factory farming, certainly not factory farming per se.  It’s animal farming: any kind of animal farming has its problems. We, as animal advocates or environmental advocates, we understand sprawl. We understand sprawl and yet we don’t see it when it is happening with farms that are being spread out. We’ll say: `Well, that is a step in the right direction.` Well, how can that be, if we in the United States are outnumbered by farmland animals, 5 to 1? So, how could it be that the problem is intensive farming? That it is a step in the right direction to have the pasture-based farms when walking around, three hundred million of us in this country, and we are outnumbered 5 to 1, and that is just the land farm animals? So the problem isn’t the factory. The problem is both. If you have concentrated farms you have dense runoff, you have emissions—you do have emissions, and they may be controlling them to some extent but they are still there—you still have ruminant animals, and they are emitting methane. There is fine particulate matter that goes up to the air, and all the things that lead to acid rain.

Caryn Hartglass: And they still make manure, piles of it.

Lee Hall: No matter how they are raised. If you’ve got farm expansion…

Caryn Hartglass: The shit continues.

Lee Hall: It’s in either one. When you’ve got the expanded farms, the pasture-based, the grass-fed, you’ve got other situations. The destruction, and of course, with the intensive farm you have all the humane questions—the whole idea that humanity would treat animals as things to put into tiny boxes that is there—but when you have expansion, at the end we kill them, so it is a myth that it can be humane, because they are being slaughtered at the end. But there is more: when you expand the farm you are fragmenting habitat. You are setting the stage for systematic predator control, followed by a cascade of consequences.

Caryn Hartglass: Wait a minute, What is systematic predator control?

Felis silvestris

Bobcat. On pastures, “free-range” farm animals are captive targets of undomesticated predators; in turn, the predators become persecuted by your local animal farmers and their supporting agencies.

Lee Hall: Well, for example, coyotes and foxes are the animals who are normally targeted.With coyotes in pastures, they are irritating to farmers. Obviously. A coyote, bobcat, fox, a grizzly bear is going to be tempted, understandably, to eat an animal; so the more free-range the farm is, the more vulnerable they are…Shooting coyotes is legal in most places; coyotes can be shot from aircraft; there are forms of poison. The very first coyote synthetic attractant, a lure to attract and kill them, debuted in 1973 and was made from the fatty acids of rhesus monkeys’ vaginal secretions. Since then we have come up with all kinds of traps and lures to attract coyotes and foxes. One infamous one called Compound 1080 goes into predacide collars, and those are strapped to free-range goats and lambs. So here is this poison: it will not save the goat or the lamb; the point is the coyote goes to the animal and if the coyote bites the neck of that farm animal that coyote is about to enter Hell. The poison takes somewhere between 3 and 15 hours to kill. Then there are the traps, the snares, the M44—another lure.  Wildlife Services, our federal government, helps the ranchers. These poisons are often picked up by pets, bald eagles, turkey vultures, wolves—unintended animals. Migratory birds, porcupines, mountain lions. So all these things are happening out there with these free-range farms. To say “Well, stop factory farming” totally ignores that.

Caryn Hartglass:  Wow, and who thinks up these things,? Who thinks up these poisons and these traps? The thing I was wondering about is who are these scientists, these educated scientists that invent these incredible killing materials? The minds that come up with these things …Yes. So there are all these “compassionate” people, who want to get humanely-raised animals and go for pastures. But there are all these issues with that. Of course, there are the intensified farms and there are all animal farms and when we look at it from an environmental point of view the winner is the one no one is looking at, which is feeding plants to people directly.

Shirt created by nonviolenceunited.org

The winner. Design by nonviolenceunited.org

Lee Hall: Exactly. People are looking at it, just maybe not in a way that connects it directly to their plate. I am in school now studying with scientists and lawyers. I am seeing that the people in environment law course are aware. For example: There is a study by Christopher Weber and Scott Matthews at Carnegie Mellon and they have done calculations of greenhouse gas emissions and they have said a “protein shift”—and that is their word for it, when you get protein and nutrients directly from plants instead of feeding it to animals and getting all the nutrients through them—when you do this protein shift one day a week it would be like driving 1,160 miles less every year. What they are talking about is sort of like a vegan Monday. They are saying: Replace meat and dairy and this is what would happen 1,160 less miles a year. So that suggests that animal agribusiness per se is non-local…

If you cut it out even one day it would be more than a thousand miles saved driving so right there they are getting somewhere. So this is what I bring up when we are having these conversations: Wait a minute! That means a 7-day-a-week shift is more than eight thousand miles as though you were not driving every year, more than eight thousand miles. If you have that kind of power that a vegan diet can have, and anyone can have that kind of power, and they can have it a dinnertime, they could decide right now, why not? Being vegan in North America is not a real big difficulty, and it would decrease all of this harm all of these climate chaos caused by the taking away of habitat of other animals. It’s ranching: taking away the other animals’ habitat is what it does. In the last five hundred years more animals have gone extinct in the US, more than any other place; we are wrecking this land and water for ranching.

Caryn Hartglass: You know this show is called It’s All About Food but it’s really all about money, and the animal food industry is a 160-billion-dollar-a-year industry in the US, and I think I am going to be talking to these cattle producers and telling them we need to reduce or eliminate animal livestock, and I am getting right to the heart of their livelihood. What do we tell people like that?

Lee Hall: Right. There has always been forms of livelihood that the economy has depended on that we had to say: There is a problem with this. We need to transcend this, and start acting differently. You can think of three or four examples right now. The chocolate slavery is not okay. It comes from massive chocolate companies and they are selling loads and loads of chocolate at the expense of people on the Ivory Coast that are selling their children into slavery. It’s not okay.

Caryn Hartglass: It’s not okay. But you know most people don’t know about it. It has taken a long time to get Hershey’s Chocolate to budge.

Lee Hall:  Yes. And when you are out there talking to two hundred cattle ranchers, you have people that are talking to many, many more. … A lot of people, including  environmentalists, need to know this it is not just the cattle ranchers that you are informing, that you are having these conversations with; you are talking about getting to a tipping point. And because climate change is upon us, we may be right about at the tipping point.

Caryn Hartglass:  There are plenty of people, and there is one guy on the panel that I will be talking to is a climate change denier. And doesn’t believe it is happening.

Lee Hall: Yes. Who is now connected to the Food and Agriculture representing the UN.

Caryn Hartglass: And it is really hard to know. We live in a very complex world. There is a lot of information on the Internet but it takes a lot to figure out what is credible and what is not; I can’t go into every lab and see what they are doing. When I read things in a study, that I think are interesting. I will go to the original source and read all I can when the study was done and see if I think it was good or not if it is something that I want to repeat. Most people don’t do that. But still I can’t see everything….

Lee Hall: We do know that the carbon dioxide level in our atmosphere is at the highest point in more than 600 thousand years. We do know that global average temperatures, even though they fluctuate madly, are higher than they have been over ten thousand years.

Caryn Hartglass: There are people that do not believe that. I have seen that data and I believe it. But some people see it and still say they do not believe it.

Lee Hall: Well, it is becoming a part of policy.

Caryn Hartglass: There are—95% of climate change scientists that think the climate is changing.

Lee Hall: It becomes: how much it is from animal farming? And the consensus seems to be about 1/5 but as you know specialists from the world bank including Robert Goodland, who unfortunately passed away recently, had said more like 51% is attributable to animal agribusiness. So Mark Bittman invited Robert Goodland to do a blog on Mark Bittman’s column for the New York Times, and Robert Goodland wrote: One might expect the Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations to work objectively to determine whether the true figure is 1/5 or 51%. Instead, Mittloehner, known for the claiming that the 1/5th is too big of a figure to use in the US, was announced as chair of a new partnership between the meat industry and the UN Food and Agriculture Organization. So Mark Bittman titled that guest blog FAO Yields to Meat Industry Pressure on Climate Change; it is very frightening .

Caryn Hartglass: It is frightening. We are going to have to talk about this more another time because we are out of time. Can you believe it?

Lee Hall: No.

Caryn Hartglass: I know. I am going to have to have you back and dig more into this, especially after I am on this panel with Frank Mittloehner and see what he has to say.  Lee, thank you so much for joining us for this have hour as for all the work you are doing some time soon and we can have some delicious food vegan food the best.

Lee Hall:  Wonderful Idea. Meanwhile, I am rooting for the Lone Vegan.

Caryn Hartglass: We have come to the end of It’s All About Food.  Thank you for joining me.  I am Caryn, and remember: Please have a delicious week.


Caryn Hartglass

Caryn Hartglass

ABOUT THE INTERVIEWER: Cancer survivor and vegan activist Caryn Hartglass founded Responsible Eating And Living (REAL) as a 501(c)3 not-for-profit corporation. For 9 years Hartglass served as Executive Director of the nonprofit EarthSave International, founded by John Robbins. Hartglass has appeared on Dr. Oz, Geraldo At Large, 20-20 and CNN and is the host of It’s All About Food on the Progressive Radio Network. Caryn Hartglass can multitask, showing your group how to make healthy, delicious foods, while inspiring you to do so. Have Caryn Hartglass speak at your next event. For more information send email to info@RealMeals.org or call 657- I M 4 REAL (657-464-7325).

Animals as Pets: Transcript From the 2008 London Vegan Festival

The 11th annual London Vegan Festival was held on Sunday, 7 September 2008 at Kensington Town Hall, and this is a presentation and dialogue I was offered the opportunity to facilitate. I added footnotes later for readers’ further information. Participants were informed of the sound recording both at the beginning and conclusion of the talk, which was originally published through the Australian web-based magazine Abolitionist Online, Issue 6 (Dec. 2008).

Part One: Rescue and Domination, Welfare and Rights

Lee Hall: The question here is: Must animal advocates choose between being rescuers and working for animal rights?

Why would there be a distinction between working to rescue animals and working for animal rights? Well, I don’t think there is. I live with cats. They were all street cats, and I love them. And I don’t mind saying that; I’m proud of saying that because I’m and animal-rights activist who’s also for animal welfare. What I don’t say, what I don’t do, is credit industries with doing anything for animal welfare. The welfare they’re looking out for is the welfare of their shareholders. So if an industry that commodifies animals, sells animals as meat, if somebody who works in animal experimentation says they’re working for animal welfare—they don’t. The vocabulary is really important. When you’re looking at an institution of use, you’re looking at animal husbandry. Not animal welfare.

What I do by looking after the cats I live with is truly animal welfare. So this is a taking back of the word welfare.

You’ve heard people say, “Oh they’re a welfarist organization; don’t listen to them.” Well, I’m a welfarist. I look after domesticated animals who need a home. But I don’t credit the institutions that use domesticated animals with being interested in their welfare. So if somebody says something about an animal-welfare law or an animal-welfare rule, and the animal is still within the institution of use, I would call that a husbandry rule, not a welfare rule—you see the distinction, that we shouldn’t credit the industries with animal welfare.

This is a really, really big distinction. Because even in the abolitionist movement, you know there is this question of advocates who are working for animal welfare and advocates who are working for animal rights. How many people have heard about this, welfare and rights? [Several hands are raised.] That there’s this difference, right? So I’m saying that the word welfare being used in the sense of “Let’s work for modifications within the industry”—I don’t think that is welfare, so maybe there’s not this hard-line distinction between animal welfare and animal rights if one uses the words properly.

So I’m for animal rights; I am an abolitionist. I would like to see the end of animal use. But for animals who are captive and are dependent on us for the rest of their lives, I agree with animal welfare in their circumstances. For pets, I agree with animal welfare. That’s the best we can extend to them. They are not going to have animal rights.

What I see as animal rights is the right to live on your own terms, not on the terms of the people who have subjugated you.

It seems a very important distinction here, and I don’t think it’s being talked about very much. And I thought that the reason for writing a second book—I’ve written one, and also co-authored a vegan cookbook, and my next book will be called On Their Own Terms—is the view is that animal rights is an ideal, for which we should all strive, that respects animals’ rights to live on their terms and not on the terms of people who have subjugated them.

In the meantime, the animals we have brought into existence—as pets, as animals used as food—we have a responsibility to look after. I don’t agree that they should be killed. I think we should look after them for the rest of their lives and that’s why I live with animals bred as pets.

Should you call animals “pets”? I don’t know; should you call people who are enslaved “slaves”? The truth. Should we call them companion animals? Well, “companion” is a word that means some sort of mutual decision we’ve reached that we’re going to live together and break bread together, that’s com-pan-ion. The root is to share bread.

A feral kitten looks out from beneath an apartment block.

Did they decide that they were going to live with me? Is it fair that I call them a companion—an animal companion or a companion animal? Did they make the decision to share bread with me? They didn’t. They were on the streets and they got injured and they showed up at my door. And I was a vegan for ten years when I took the first one in. I’d wanted to avoid taking in cats. And once I took one in because I couldn’t find someone else, then I was already in the situation of looking after a domesticated cat, and felt that this is a person, an individual. And I thought, well, I’ve put this person in this situation of dependency, because I am in the class; we define ourselves as humans. What does the word mean?

Darwin said human is a species, right? But species is a category of convenience. There’s no actual line between species; it’s a continuum.[1] It’s constructed; and how do we construct ourselves? We decided that we’re the species that’s in charge of everybody else, and therefore we can own others. We first decided we are the species in charge of everybody else; in other words, we’re dominating the others. And we decided this why? Because we wanted to protect ourselves against the wolves and the wildcats. And so now we’ve domesticated them, and made them into dogs and cats. Smaller beings.

How many people have heard of Temple Grandin? About five? Temple Grandin is the person who designs slaughterhouses, right?

Participant: Isn’t Temple Grandin in the animal-welfare movement?

Lee: Is Temple Grandin for the welfare of animals?

Participant: I wouldn’t define slaughter in any circumstance as welfare. It’s not in the welfare of any particular individual to be killed.

Lee: Let’s say that Temple Grandin works in the animal-husbandry field. Yes, George—

George Rodger: Isn’t that the lady who claims to be—to telepath with animals?

Lee: Yes. Autistic?

George: Yes, well, that as well.

Lee: Yes. Temple Grandin wrote a book called Genetics and Behavior of Domestic Animals, and said that the genetic studies point to the wolves as the ancestors of domestic dogs. And through a process called neoteny, there’ve been changes in a few genes.

This has happened throughout the centuries of selective breeding—specifically since the Victorian era. Dogs were domesticated 15,000 years ago, cats less; the modern breeds of cats and dogs we see, however, have come into existence in about the past 200 years.

And Temple Grandin says that during domestication—this process that actually started 15,000 years ago with the dogs—what are selected are infantile behaviours. In other words, when you see dogs they yap, they bark all their lives, whereas with wolves, they only bark and yap as small babies, cubs. So they’ve retained this babyhood. And the dogs we see today are in this sense permanently babies. So we’re taking them from their world of the wolves—and they can’t go back. You can see dogs go out and live with other dogs, street dogs, but they don’t turn back into wolves. And domesticated cats never become wildcats, and that’s where they came from.

In domestic dogs, the social behaviour patterns are fragmented and incomplete, Temple Grandin says. There have been studies done—which I don’t approve, as I’m a vegan who subscribes to the views of The Vegan Society, that is, opposing animal testing of any kind—but I’ll let you know what Temple Grandin said about malamutes: When raised with wolf pups, they failed to read the social cues of wolves; they couldn’t comprehend what wolves were saying. And their physical development was slower. So malamutes, who are close to wolves in looks and apparently in genetics, still couldn’t keep up with what the wolves were saying.

Yorkshire terriers retain their baby teeth.

Patricia Tricker [who’s from Yorkshire]: Just make me cringe.

Lee: Not to pick on you.

Patricia: They look like little—hairy rats—

Participant: Aww—

Patricia: It’s not the fault of the dog –

Lee: No, right, it’s a deformation.

Patricia: Yeah. I mean, it’s not my idea of what a dog should look like.

Lee: From wolves—I understand the point you’re making, Patricia—the farther they got from wolves the more deformed, this is true, biologically; the handout we’ve got shows certain kinds of dogs who are so far removed from wolves that for example the bulldogs have trouble giving birth and need caesarean sections. The BBC recently did an exposé of [the British dog show] Crufts. And it got to the point where the Queen was thinking of separating from the Kennel Club. Because the BBC was saying, well, there are certain dogs, for example, the cavalier King Charles spaniels are built so that their little heads are so small that their brains are squeezed against the back of their spines, and there’s this fluid that goes into the spinal cord, and, as they said on the BBC, about half of these spaniels have this condition. It causes excruciating pain, to the point where it’s like hitting someone on the head with a sharp object repeatedly, and the cavalier King Charles spaniels are given human painkillers for their entire lives because there is no dog’s painkiller for this condition; however, this condition has happened in humans so they know what kind of drugs to give. Imagine: They live with this their entire lives.

So when Patricia said “there are certain dogs that just make me cringe” the Yorkshire terrier being one of them, there’s a reason Patricia is saying that. And it’s not directed at the individual. There’s a difference between who you are and what you are: As an individual, the dog is a person who deserves love and care; certainly these spaniels deserve everything we can do—except now, they’re in a most non-vegan position. I understand Donald Watson lived for 95 years and never took any pharmaceutical drugs, concerned that they were tested on animals. So here you have the pharmaceutical companies selling drugs with which we alleviate the pain that these spaniels feel all their lives.

One of the breed sites for Yorkshire terriers says: “These dogs must be allowed to live indoors. They cannot tolerate heat or cold. Besides, they are much happier with their family.”

Now think about that. Their family. They were separated from their family. Taken from their mother. Taken from their siblings. And put in certain homes. And now we say that’s our family.

We treat them with love, as we would treat a member of our family; I do. But I know what their family members went through—what they went through, and they were the ones spared from what others went through; that’s why they live with me—because they survived it.

So, are they ever in the position to make the choice? They are put in front of us, for people to select, buy, and take home. Some of them don’t make it that far. They’re vivisected; they watch car parks, behind barbed wire fences, on oily concrete, every night. They stay alive as long as they live with somebody who cares. And for every one of them, many relatives don’t make it.

Sprite & Elf

I rescued them. But that means, in a sense, I dominate them; because in the act of rescue, one party becomes dominant, and the other party becomes dependent on that rescue. And I have one pair of siblings, and one of the pair loves being inside. Plays all the time, always asking me to play. They are siblings, born together, and they both came in at approximately the same time. I heard one calling for the other—didn’t know what the ruckus was, and then the other one showed up at the door and they looked very much alike (that’s why it first seemed there was only one) and when I brought the second one in, the ruckus stopped. All the howling, the screaming had gone on non-stop for a month. That’s how much the one cared about having the other one. And when they were together it stopped. W ell, they have two different personalities. The one who was screaming isn’t particularly happy to be inside. This one, it seems, doesn’t like to be dominated. But the other one is inside and appears to have a different perspective: I like the food; I like to play; I like the other cats here and I’m enjoying myself. So there are two, with different interests, but I know what they seem to like best of all and that’s to be together. So they’ll have a place for life. Including the one who didn’t seem to want to be in, and probably would have been the survivor. But I can’t split them up; they love each other.

Well, in human circumstances, the ideal rescue would be you help somebody and then immediately allow them to regain their independence. As quickly as possible, you assist them to go back to independence. In this case, we have feral cats who live on average two years where I live in North America; whereas if they’re inside it could be up to 20 years. So I’m making a decision and imposing it on them, one who seems thrilled with it, the other one, I think it’s going to take time. So I’m imposing it. The two of them could never live in a natural bio-community and have a full life. Where I live, that one who wants to be out would be picked up, and gone. So, the dilemma.

Free-living animals, on the other hand, if you rescue them, for example, a sea lion on the coast wrapped up in lines—there’s no nice word for “fishing”—this is another reason to become a vegan: The killing of the fish means sea lions, pelicans, and everybody else is getting hooks in their throats. At Friends of Animals, our group, the Marine Animal Rescue team, picks up pelicans and sea lions.[2] They can’t help the fish because the problem for the fish is the demand. So when they help the pelicans, sea lions, and whales, what they also say is: Stop eating the fishes. For their own sake, we shouldn’t be in the ocean, bringing animals out and eating them. And for the sake of these other animals.Marine Animal Rescue

So they’ll find a few animals paralysed, do x-rays and find a hook in the spine. They’ll take the hook out, and the animal will go back into the sea. As quickly as possible, you’re sending the animal back to the completely free circumstances. Now you’re talking about an animal who can experience animal rights.

In a world where we had animal rights, sea lions could experience it. If we all agreed on animal rights, see lions could flourish. And they would.

And we’d have a much more robust environmental movement, because if we respected free-living animals, and their right to be living on their own terms, that would necessarily mean that we protect and respect their habitat. That, for the first time in history, would give polluters their true challenge. If animal rights were injected into environmentalist thinking, for the first time, we’d have a powerful environmental movement. And animal rights needs to bring environmentalism into its thinking, because animal rights is going to be found with the sea lions, it’s going to be found with the wolves. The dogs can never go back.

The dogs are individuals. We look after them as unique individuals. But they’ll never have animal rights.

There are only a few wildcats in Britain. About 400. They live in Scotland. They were exterminated in Wales and England; people thought evil spirits lived in the wildcats, or that they might diminish the number of animals used for food, get on the land of the farmer and cause trouble, or maybe they’d eat human beings; that was thought too. And that’s not far from the truth, because we’re not at the top of the food chain. We’re primates, and in the world there are humans who are killed by big cats. We don’t like to think that we’re subject to risk, but if we seriously respected free-living animals, we’d understand and accept that we are, and we’d live with that risk.

In Britain there are no wolves left except behind fences. There are 400 wildcats. And you know what the greatest threat to their survival is? You’d be surprised.

Patricia: Encroachment, lack of habitat.

Lee: That’s closely connected, and always behind everything, yes: lack of habitat. Specifically, the international groups protecting big cats have said that, globally, the one biggest threat is the mix of genes with domesticated cats. So now in Scotland there may be a mandatory rule to spay and neuter cats simply to keep them away from the wildcats. Because there are only 400, and only in Scotland—the only place the gamekeepers didn’t completely wipe them out.

So there you have another reason for stopping or for challenging this domestication.

How many people have read or heard of Jeffrey Masson…who says there is one example of domesticated animals who might be very close to the situation of having animal rights in their lives, and that would be the domesticated cats allowed to roam freely. But here’s the rub. We’ve changed them genetically just enough so that they can never return to being wildcats. Yet they can still procreate with wildcats; here we go again with the invasive research, now going on in Scotland, to find out how many of these wildcats really are wildcats, and not the progeny of some domesticated parent. So you see: Some of them do live close to independently of us, but it turns out that we have created an imbalance in the biocommunity that threatens to wipe out every wildcat in the world. Everywhere wildcats are, humans have let domesticated cats outside, and abandoned them, and this challenge has occurred to the free-living community.

When environmentalists say you can’t really take animal-rights people seriously because we don’t understand anything about free-living animals, it’s a good idea to have the understanding of how domesticated animals interact with free-living animals, and how we change the biocommunity.

Patricia: I thought the Scottish wildcat was actually different from the wildcats in other countries. Is that right, that they are different? So if they were completely wiped out and there wasn’t a single one left, you couldn’t reintroduce them from anywhere else.

Lee: Now you’re bringing up another issue, and important one. Once a community is gone in a certain region, there’s a dilemma. Should you reintroduce what’s called a species, a community of individuals; should you take certain ones and treat them as specimens and put them in a certain place, expecting them to breed, possibly at the expense of lives of many of them when they’re shipped from here to there? If the Scottish wildcats go… In England, certain very wealthy people have offered their lands to bring in some of the large mammals.

Participant: Wolves.

Lee: Yeah. I’m going to go for six more minutes, then someone sound a buzzer. [Laughter.] There’s a question to cover, that’s come up in animal rights theory. How far would you take animal rights? To avoid species bias, how far do you take it? And the theorists, animal-rights authors, bring up this hypothetical question, a lot. There’s a lifeboat, with human people and a dog. The boat isn’t strong enough to hold the dog and the humans. Should you throw out the dog or a human? And you have to make a decision; someone’s got to go. Generally you’ll find —

Participant: In New Orleans they did leave the dogs behind, didn’t they? They didn’t even get into the boat.

Lee: Interesting that you bring this up because animal-rights theorists will say “That’s just a hypothetical; don’t worry too much— [Laughter] because it’s not going to happen. We can decide to pick the human, but don’t worry; it doesn’t invalidate the theory at all because this is only in any emergency; it never happens.” [Laughter] It does happen. And it’s going to happen more and more, with global warming. They just had another, and had to evacuate, and we don’t know where those dogs and cats are right now. Every hurricane season, as the Gulf of Mexico warms, the hurricanes will be more extreme.

Sarah Austin: In New Orleans, some wouldn’t leave—

Lee: Standing on top of the refrigerator with the cat. I’d like to think I’d do the same.

Well, generally they say you can throw the animal. Tom Regan, in The Case for Animal Rights in 1983, said you could and you should, ethically, throw the dog overboard. And the reason is this: There’s equality, because dogs have a sense of what Regan calls sympathy, self-sacrifice, loyalty, and courage. So to that extent the lives of other animals are equal to human lives. Still, relevant differences remain. Because the human’s life typically offers many more possible sources of satisfaction than a dog’s. So there’s a difference—between the humans and dogs being equal, and the interest in their lives being equal. And Regan says equal respect means counting their interests as equal, so if the humans have more possible sources of satisfaction, we have to look at that and account for that against how many possible sources of satisfaction a dog could get, and therefore you would have to save the human.

Well, dogs can sniff through concrete. I mean, imagine how many interests they have. [Laughter] But the dog then becomes a foil, a proof of our special status—as Regan sees it, our greater variety of sources of satisfaction. We can listen to Bach. A dog doesn’t care about Bach.

Whatever we might think of Regan’s view, it’s at least true that Regan has carved out an exception to the rule of equality there. It’s not part of the theory, the fabric, of animal rights. It’s a hole in the fabric.

Gary Francione, in 2000, in Introduction to Animal Rights: Your Child or the Dog, didn’t go so far as Regan and say that you should—that it’s your ethical responsibility to —throw the dog overboard. Francione said no, it’s not; you can decide. But if you decide the dog can be thrown overboard because the dog is a dog and not a human, that doesn’t invalidate animal rights. Because it’s an emergency, it happens infrequently. [Laughter]

Well, it’s not infrequent. And it’s one thing to say I’ll throw a random individual out; it’s another thing to say, as Francione said, that the dog can be thrown overboard every time—because the dog is a dog and not a human—and that doesn’t invalidate animal rights.[3] It’s certainly a hole in the fabric.

Because there’s a 19th-century case in English criminal law called Regina vs. Dudley and Stevens. (Generally, the United States and part of Canada have accepted English law.) There were four people stranded in a lifeboat. All sailors. But the youngest one, Parker, who was still a teenager, wasn’t seasoned, and drank seawater; a fatal mistake. And the other three figured: that one’s a goner. And they’d already caught a turtle whose body they consumed.

One of the group said it would be wrong to kill Parker, for you don’t kill a living person, even a barely living person. But the other two felt their chances of survival were better if they did, rather than let Parker become fully diseased, dead, and then eat the body and drink the blood. So they waited for the naysayer to go to sleep, and then agreed to take their next chance and kill Parker. They were desperate, and they killed. They consumed Parker’s body. And they did live. And they said, we needed to do it or we’d have all been dead.

The judges back in England hadn’t decided this particular question before. The people were sympathetic to the survivors and didn’t want to see them sentenced. Most of the testimony indicated the young sailor was unconscious already when killed, though there was some debate, some question as to whether Parker had managed to protest. But what was clear is that Parker was dying. And the court said that’s murder.

The implication was that the group ought to have drawn straws, as had been done in an earlier case, so that no one would have died involuntarily. The court’s stated decision was that “necessity” is no defence to a charge of murder.

Now if we were out in the boat and we came back and the human was gone and we’d saved a dog, there’d be very little sympathy. Most people would say that was wrong; you shouldn’t have sacrificed the human to save the dog. So we can see why theorists say what they say. The theorists are saying, well, I don’t want to say that we should in any circumstances kill a human being. Because that would make the general public think that vegans, animal-rights authors are crazy.

But they say, “No, it doesn’t invalidate the theory.”

Look at the idea. If we say it’s acceptable to kill the dog because the dog is a dog, then we’ve basically said you can do vivisection. Because you have laid the groundwork for the person doing the vivisection to say, “But an emergency might come up and I need to do what I’m doing, because when an emergency comes up, then I’ve done my job: to save people from a life-threatening disease.”

That’s what happens every day. Because we have decided that one can go over the side of the boat. This view is below the surface of how we treat other animals every single day. It’s not just an emergency. It’s what we think. Because we were raised to think that we are in a superior position. It’s a tautology. Because the dog’s a dog, when push comes to shove, that dog will go overboard.

That’s what humans think. What can we do about that? Well maybe the question should be—Donald Watson, I think, would look at the root of this question. Tom Regan said the boat is not like the lab, because animals in the lab had already been made into tools. Their interests were already compromised. Not like the lifeboat where the dog is being helped, so don’t compare it to a lab.

Well, over 15,000 years, this wolf was changed into a Pekingese. And that’s not an abrogation of their rights, of their personhood? And although it was very slow—over 15,000 years—was that not a sort of violence that put the dog in the position of reliance, of needing rescue? And shouldn’t the question be: Why did we do that?

A lot of people of New Orleans can’t or won’t save the dogs. We know this is going to happen. A lot of them won’t make the decision to stand on the refrigerator.

Should human beings be in charge of what once were wolves? Should we put them in that position?

The alarm went off; that’s great. So we’re gonna have a discussion about this.

This is the question I think animal activists aren’t quite ready for: Should we continue to domesticate animals?

Part Two: Group Discussion

Here’s the BBC. They’re exposing Crufts, because of the King Charles spaniels, bulldogs and so on. They’re not into animal rights. But they’re saying at least for some breeds: We think this is an abomination. Now animal activists haven’t really gone there, so the BBC is leading the argument.

I know a lot of animal lawyers and speak with them on panels. What do they think of dogs and cats? Generally, that dogs and cats should be made beneficiaries of wills. They think these animals should not be called pets, that they should instead be called companion animals because it’s more respectful; and they think these animals should have some sort of rights vis-à-vis their “guardians”; they don’t say owners. So, what they’re not doing is going to the root and asking: Should these animals be in these circumstances at all? Because they will always be needing a home, food. Shelter, roofs over their heads. They are not going to return to their biocommunity and live on their own terms. They’re going to live on ours. The animal lawyers aren’t looking at this question.

The BBC is looking at it only to an extent— to certain breeds. What would be interesting? Breed-specific legislation, called, you know, BSL —

Sarah: Yeah, what about not doing it in the first place, breeding.

Lee Hall: Yes, I agree with you. We shouldn’t kill them, because they’re individuals—

Sarah: Oh, no; it’s just that we wouldn’t breed any more.

Lee: But because they’ve come in one breed by one, selectively created. You know there are new breeds of cats just over the past several years. So if that’s the way they came into existence, one by one, then this breed-specific legislation, which some people call speciesist or discriminatory, is it really?

This is a rough issue. But if we are going to stop the breeding of pets into existence, would that not mean starting with the animals who can’t even give birth without caesarian sections, or go through massive headaches—and headache seems too mild a term for what King Charles spaniels go through—should we not say maybe what the BBC is implying is right? Why are they here?

Sarah: Haven’t we got to get on the breeders, then? Their specific breeders? I mean, surely they’re only doing it for money.

Patricia: Well, the problem comes from people who want to go out and get a dog, a puppy, a specific breed, rather than going out and rescuing.

Sarah: It might not be the individual’s fault. People might not be aware of the situation because they’re not a breeder themselves.

Patricia: But if people can read I should think they would be aware of what those people are doing.

Sarah: They might not be aware, but they’re still creating a need.

Patricia: Isn’t it obvious, though? I can’t imagine anyone not realizing how obvious it is that if you pay five, six, seven hundred pounds for a pedigreed dog, somebody is actually making money from you. If you go out and buy something else that’s 700 pounds, you know someone’s actually making a profit… They do know it. “But we so desperately want a Yorkshire terrier” or —

Catriona Gold: It’s just an excuse in this day and age. Everyone knows about abandoned dogs and cats needing homes.

Participant: I think it all comes back to animal-rights being about you have to educate people that, actually, it’s all wrong, keeping pets. But that’s such a hard thing to do; I mean, you know, we haven’t turned that many people vegan yet so how are we ever going to stop them keeping pets? Because pets, they’re the nice lives— farm animals, yes, they get slaughtered, but pets are cosy.

Lee: Although breeding them into existence means millions are killed every year.

Participant: But even with the rescue centres, I mean, a friend of mine wanted a kitten for their child to grow up with. You can’t get a kitten from the rescue centre to grow up with your child, it has to be a cat, and a cat who gets on with children, so they said, oh, we’re going to go to the pet shop and buy one.

Participant: Surely not all the breeds are— manufactured, if you like, to our specifications, are they? Big heads, small ears, little legs or whatever you want.

Patricia: These are the ones that have really very serious problems, serious health problems. But there are other breeds as well. There was something I heard recently about Rhodesian ridgebacks, that they can have a particular spine problem.

Participant: But Labradors—

Patricia: The thing about Labradors is that they’re very short-lived dogs. You know, they’re really old if they’re ten.

[Crosstalk.]

Participant: A dog on a farm, they really have a hard life compared to a home life.

Roy: A cat would be meowing outside our house for days on end. Eventually we asked the neighbours if we should let the cat in, to provide a place to sleep, in order to possibly get away from their new dog, and they said just to ignore it, but the cat would meow all night. Eventually the cat’s sister came in through the cat flap that was part of our house. In the end, the cats just stayed around forever. [Laughter] When we tried to take them next door, it was evident that they were frightened of the dog. I fed them because I felt really guilty eating in front of the cats. [Laughter] I really didn’t want to have an animal, and I was in this predicament, as a vegan not wanting to buy meat. And I wondered what other people feel. Do you buy organic, or…

Lee: What you bring up is probably in my top five reasons for challenging the whole idea of animals as pets. Now, there’s going to be a difference of opinion in this room as to whether we should be getting vegan cat food or not. But you’re talking about animals who’ve been bred from carnivores. Even if you were to feed them vegan cat food, you’d be making them into little vegans who fit your lifestyle, like the lawyers who try to bring them into wills.

Is the root issue what you’re feeding your cat? Or is the issue all these cats all over the world and all the people who are beholden to animal agribusiness — not just for themselves but for their cats? And this is the case for vegans as well. I moved from a one-bedroom spot; I rent a house. Small, one-story, part is an office so it’s functional; but the point is, I can live in one room. The cats weren’t happy there. [Laughter] Nine cats and I was doing trap-neuter-return and as much fostering as possible.

So we’re talking about taking up a bigger space on Earth. Yet what we’re doing as vegans is reducing the space we take on Earth for a number of reasons. One, to leave habitat for free-living animals who could appreciate that space and survive.

Sarah: So do you feed them tinned food? I mean, that’s a big issue.

Lee: I know it’s an issue. And I’m not going to go into that debate. But it’s not the issue. We’ll talk about it privately. [Laughter] I know, every time this comes up people come to blows.

The issue is deeper than that. Even if you decide to give domesticated animals vegan food there are also people who aren’t. And vegan food itself takes up space, to grow whatever it is we’re giving to domesticated animals. There are 6.6 billion of us. We are outnumbered three-to-one, globally—four-to-one in affluent countries—by farm animals alone. This doesn’t include the animals bred as pets. Look at the footprint of 6.6 billion of us and multiply it, because we’ve got this entourage of domesticated animals.

So we take much more space than we need, much more food than we need, when there are people who are just trying to eat enough every day, and we’re running into a global food shortage which will be exacerbated by global warming.

Lisa (moderator): A few things. We’re the last speaker in the room today, so I think it’s OK if we go over time. If everyone’s aware, it’s almost five, if they want to run up to something else. And also, another comment: We’re talking about domestic animals, cats and dogs, taking up space in terms of, you have to grow food for them to eat. I’m interested to see what other people think about what are known as community dogs in developing nations. I was living in the Pacific for the past year, and in one house I lived in, we had a pack of five to ten dogs that would come around every few days to multiple houses in the area, and they’d eat the leftover food, they would go through the garbage. People never fed them, like they never went out and bought tinned food or cooked up anything particular for them. But they seemed to be quite happy, healthy, independent dogs who hung out with whoever they chose to associate with.

Patricia: But were they wandering around the streets on their own? Yes, well, I’ve seen dogs wandering around the streets in this country. It’s not as common as it used to be. Where I was brought up, on a very working-class, big housing estate, people used to let the dogs run around, and it was not a pretty sight. I’ve seen them in Spain, where they just run around all over the roads and cause accidents. Well, OK, it’s not the dogs causing accidents, it’s the drivers, we know that. And certainly as individuals they can be very aggressive. Now, again, this is the humans’ fault, because of the way they’re treated; it’s not the dogs’ fault. It does make it rather difficult to live in this sort of situation.

George: In other words, these dogs you refer to, community dogs, they’re trying to live as wolves, which Lee was saying they’re not capable of. Living in a pack, going around scavenging, and probably if there’s the odd rabbit about they might well hunt it. They’re probably not very efficient as wolves because of being bred.

Participant: Exactly; they’re not—

George: They have all these defects—

Lee: And this is the thing with the cats, so they’re around bins.

George: I was going to mention the cats. You spoke of animals being free to live on their own terms. Well, to my mind, a cat living on its own terms is living out in the wild, in the environment, hunting smaller animals, killing them and eating them, needing a lot of space and not being very friendly towards other cats except during the mating season, and if it’s female, raising a pack, a litter of young every so often. You made a passing reference to feral cats; you said they only live two years. That’s probably not doing too badly for an animal living in the wild. A cat living 20 years in captivity would be exceptional. Most animals living in the wild don’t even reach adulthood. So any animal that can live for two years is probably surviving quite a bit longer than a lot of others that die just as kittens or as pups or whatever. And the fact that the cat can interbreed with the Scottish wildcat I think shows that by definition they are the same species, although not the same sub-species. And does it really matter if the Scottish wildcat becomes a mongrel breed rather than the pure genetic breed that it was historically?

There’s a campaign against the hunting of the ruddy duck in this country, and not s’long ago I was at a stall which had a petition against this. The ruddy duck is a North American species that’s become naturalized in this country. It’s also spread to Spain where it’s interbreeding with the native species of white-tailed duck.Ruddy duck_

Patricia: It’s the other end. It’s the white-billed duck.

George: White-billed duck. Anyway, I think it’s the RSPB being accused of trying to cull the ruddy ducks to prevent them from interbreeding with the pure-bred European duck. Whereas many animal-rights or vegan people would say, well, does it really matter if the European duck becomes a hybridized duck? In fact biologically it’s probably better to be a mixed breed rather than an in-bred, like all these highly inbred dogs that you were talking about, or the BBC was talking about.

Patricia: It is a huge dilemma, because the humans have caused the problem in the first place by bringing the ruddy ducks from North America. They wouldn’t have got here under their own steam, or paddle power. And it’s the same with a lot of species that have been introduced.

Lee: And if they had enough habitat, animals will have their natural biological diversity. The planet allows it.

George: No matter how much habitat you’ve got, these species will try to fill the habitat. So if you magically doubled the habitat available for a particular species, they will rapidly increase their number to fill it.

Lee: There’s also the question of if the predators aren’t here, you’re going to get a different dynamic—

George: Overpopulation, which is what you get with red deer in the highlands.

Catriona: Well, not necessarily, because natural competition from individual animals will drive the population down if there isn’t enough food for them.

Lee: In England, some of the predators are completely gone.

George: Nearly all the big predators are gone.

Lee: It’s a lot to think about, and we haven’t even started these debates in animal rights, because a lot of animal activists are very busy talking about changing the rules within industry, to get better husbandry for animals who are bred as food, and rights for pets…Even abolitionists have assumed the question as your child or the dog. Is that the basic question of animal rights?

There’s a lot of talk about apes’ rights—you know, they’re talking about making a law in Spain that nonhuman apes can’t be vivisected, can’t be used for entertainment. And Francione, who’s an abolitionist, who wants to abolish the use of other animals by humans completely, will say, basically, while apes know each other and are complex and so forth yet I can see when I look a dog that they are self-aware; and that they have an idea of the future; dogs know if I’m coming to the door and they anticipate pleasure. Which is true. Dogs, animals raised for farms—all have moral significance. But when we’re talking about an animal who will always depend on us for their well-being, that’s an animal-welfare question. And it has been mixed into the abolitionist theory, without careful distinctions between (a.) the reality of moral significance and (b.) the potential of legal rights. So it’s not surprising that people throughout the full spectrum of animal advocacy think that dogs could have rights.

You might hear that a director of a sanctuary is truly serious because the person really wants true rights for farm animals. But what is a right for farm animals? A purpose-bred animal is brought into the world for a human purpose. The hen who goes onto the free range suffers osteoporosis. These hens are selectively bred to produce so many eggs that the calcium goes out of the body and into the eggshells. So what you gain in extra space for the free-range hen you lose when their bones tend to break. Are you ever going to get rights for such an animal, or does the idea of purpose-breeding preclude that?

George brings up an interesting point, whether there is a grey area with certain animals. I saw some feral roosters, or cocks, in Key West. You’d hear them crow in the morning. They seemed to be living on their own terms. We need to explore more too about the question of some forms of domestication that might actually occur naturally. But when we are talking about dogs and cats who’ve been purpose-bred, and when petkeeping as we know it with these various breeds began in the Victorian era, that seems a clear issue. That this is not on their terms.

Jeffrey Masson says cats might be close to that grey area, and yet, the wildcats will be gone, and they are not the same animals.

George: Their descendants will still live on. Their descendants will be a kind of mongrel, but they’ll still live on.

Lee: Now you have the situation with apes. We talk about apes’ rights; will there be apes in a few decades? You’ve got a situation now where Jane Goodall and USAID and the Disney corporation have gone into Africa saying in order to save the great apes, they’re going to “habituate” them: bring the eco-tourists in, have them pay to follow apes around for a few weeks, and get very close to them.

I’m picking on Jane Goodall, but maybe that’s good. Because this is someone who practically everyone thinks is an expert and an advocate. We need to know what people are thinking, and who they’ll look to for expertise when they’re talking about apes’ rights.

Are we saying, first, that these apes have to pay their way to survive? That we have to convince these countries the apes are worth their weight in eco-tourist value to keep them alive?

And if so, what are we doing to them? By habituating them, which takes two years, and a lot of them reportedly don’t make it—I’d hate to hear what they go through.

Jane Goodall has also promoted, in the United States, the CHIMP Act: The chimpanzees are taken from bio-medical research and put in what they call a sanctuary. But it’s a holding area. And it may look pretty, a lot prettier than some sanctuaries, but the U.S. government holds the titles to the chimpanzees. And Jane Goodall’s point is that at least the government is giving something back. But why are we saying that this kind of model is OK? What statement is being made?

Is this a domestication of nonhuman apes? And they’re the ones closest to having rights, the ones most advocates—in fact some countries, when they’re talking about animal rights, are thinking about the apes. What apes’ rights looks like will be the model.

But if you look in the Spanish proposal, you’ll see there’s an exception for zoos.

So you think, well, what is Goodall doing with USAID and Disney in Africa? Habituating apes so they can be looked at, gawked at, stared at? It sounds very much like the zoo. So my concern, going back to George, is that will we insist, for them to survive, that they become somewhat domesticated?

I’m open to arguments, especially now, what with writing a book that will address this. But shouldn’t I resist that de-wilding, as an animal-rights advocate? Where does it lead, when our population continues to grow, and the green connectors are built over, animals such as moose or caribou live in small pockets—

George: Same with bears.

Lee: And we say the only way they’re going to survive is under human stewardship, that that will keep them alive? And there’s an element of domestication there, as that’s probably how wolves became dogs in the first place.

You’re thinking.

Roy: Yes; two things. Some people said that, in this day and age, we’re all aware of what’s going on. But I’ve just become vegan about two years ago.

Lee: Excellent.

Roy: When I try and tell my friends about it, they just don’t want to know. So everything you’re saying here is really important, and maybe the way to deal with it is to try and educate people as to what’s going on. Then when everyone is aware of what’s going on, if they choose not to follow, there’s your answer, really. Then we’re left with having to infiltrate these areas and try and free animals.

Lee: But we need a general change of paradigm. It’s one thing to try and free animals, but then they are depending on rescue. I know you’re frustrated with the prospect here, but there’s a book called Wild Law, by Cormac Cullinan, an Irish writer who talks about Thomas Kuhn’s concept of the paradigm shift.Wild Law

In history, the paradigmatic paradigm shift was the Copernican shift. We had thought, for, you know, ever, that we were central in the universe and everything moved around us, and then Copernicus came along—by the Church, there was resistance—yet in a relatively small amount of time we revolved around the sun. Suddenly, we were no longer in the middle of everything.

So—rather than say, “Well, OK, start with free-range eggs”—telling the direct truth to enough people (and we don’t know the tipping point, it could be a small amount of people who are working on a problem) we’d change the paradigm. It’s not a continuum. It’s a radical shift. The idea that we’re not in the middle of the universe is exactly what we’re talking about today. It could actually happen in a small amount of time. And it would.

Looking at global warming, scientists are saying we have a few decades to figure out what to do and do it. Animal-rights advocates have to be central in this talk, these decisions. So we can’t be mucking with this free-range egg thing. We must be direct about how animal rights is part of environmentalism. If people would see the idea of respect, that we are not in the middle of everything, that we must respect the rest of the biocommunity and accept risk, that if the bears are around, they’re around our homes, they may do something and we may live with it, and we’ll go on…

Roy: Some people don’t see other animals that way. They see them as there to be eaten.

Lee: Yeah, they do.

Roy: Animals eat animals; granted that in this day and age we don’t need to eat animals, but how can you say that you shouldn’t be eating a pig? You can prove that the earth goes around the sun. You can say a square is not a triangle. But to prove to many people that other animals have a purpose—

Participant: And it’s the vast majority.

Hart Sussman - Man the HuntedLee: Well, there’s a book called Man the Hunted. They’re not animal-rights activists who wrote it, but the idea, and it’s well-researched, is that we, for a long period of time, until very recent times, were the prey animals of lions, leopards; so we’re not at the top of a food chain. There’s scientific truth here, that’s factual. We might think we’re superior and that everybody else is naturally subject to domination, but we can bring up scientific arguments, biological arguments, and the time is now. We are looking at climate change, so maybe the time is now, and maybe our message will be heard.

But the ethical message has to be there. Because if humanity had taken Donald Watson’s message [that the vegan ideal of non-exploitation would bring humanity to the first civilization that merits the name], we would not be in the situation we’re in now. Much is due to animal agribusiness and the idea that everything is a resource for us, that we’re central in the universe.

Roy: If we release them now and let them live the way they want to live or how they should live, or how they want to live—I mean, we’re taking over the earth; if there is no need for them then grazing land will more than probably be used for something else like growing soya and rapeseed for fuel maybe or even concreted over for more housing and there would be nowhere for animals to go therefore they would just die out.

Sarah: If they’re dependent, we’d look after them.

Roy: You know, there’s a sort of thought that vegans and vegetarians, we’re the worst thing that could happen to animals. Because they’d all die off. People would have no need for animals; if we all turned vegan —

Sarah: We wouldn’t breed them.

Participant: We need less intensive growing because we need more space —

[Crosstalk.]

Lee: Wow. OK, wait. First, we’ve got to ask about population. Donald Watson asked that question at the beginning, in the first newsletter, 1944, November the first.

George: Yeah.

Lee: It said we’re already at a crisis point; it’s got to stop populating. So that’s a vegan issue. We’re well beyond the numbers Donald Watson had. The London Zoo a few years ago had an exhibit with some humans. And you’ve gotta give credit to the director of the London Zoo, who put a placard in front of the display of humans using the term plague species. And people all over the world were up in arms over that; but they saw it, and from a respected zoological person. Now I don’t like the idea of zoos, and I don’t think Watson would like the idea, being for complete non-exploitation. But here’s a zoo director who caught on to our effect on the biosphere of which we are a part.

We’ve got to bring population in. And not in the sense of who should stop, because that’s what stopped it. For a lot of people, it is about a prejudice. It’s got to be about the global human population, nobody selected for involuntary sterilization. Otherwise, it becomes a human rights issue. So it’s got to be resolved in the human community as a whole.

You also mentioned whether vegans would be causing problems for animals’ existence, whereas people who eat them keep them around. But the opposite is true, when we’re using a third of arable land for domesticated animals we eat. That land is finite space on Earth. That land is being taken away from the free-living animals. We’re going through the sixth great extinction crisis, and this one is connected with human causes. So it’s at a much higher rate than during geological times. Edward O. Wilson, the Harvard biologist, has said that by the year 2100, we’ll lose half the number of species of plants and animals we now have. But with global warming also in effect, more than half will be gone.

And what is the greatest threat to free-living communities, and to the environment? Gidon Eshel and Pamela Martin, at the University of Chicago, showed that each person in North America releases the equivalent of four tons of carbon dioxide every year. But they said if you’re vegan, it’s 1.5 tons less.

To be easy on the climate, the most important thing we can do is to embrace a vegan diet.

Roy: I shouldn’t have said vegans would be responsible, but if we convince everyone that we don’t need to eat animals, so don’t use them, won’t we get into a situation where people say we don’t have any need for animals?

Sarah: This is probably a completely different issue but I think it’s a big one: We have the whole of history on our shoulders, with our social values and our big consumption that’s growing and growing, and meat-eating and things like that, the whole of our growth, values that permeate the whole of our society, everything on our shoulders from our history.

Lee: Yes, we’ve built our civilization on this idea of hierarchy. It’s a huge issue.

Abolitionist animal-rights activists, and specifically Gary Francione, say animals should have one right and that’s the right not to be a commodity. And this is not, in any way, meant to diminish the important work that’s gone into abolitionism so far— I agree animals should have the right not to be property; otherwise, no right’s really going to matter— but I’d like to go one further and you just touched it. Animals should have a positive right. It’s not just the right to be non-property, to be not-something; we need to start talking about what animals should have the right to be. They could be non-property and be gone, and at the rate we’re going—and you could say that every extinct animal community is not property.

More than just the right of not being commodities, there has got to be something said about domination. Yes, we have a lot of history. We dominated them and then they became commodities. So what can we do about this hierarchical mind we have? How are we going to talk with other people?

I think Donald Watson got there, talking about non-exploitation, and saying that veganism was about conscientious objection, and seeing our treatment of other animals as a war on them. That there was no border between warring on our own human community and warring on theirs and keeping them as captives. And that war needs to stop, not just between humans—although it does, and that’s really important, and a lot of people don’t advocate that—and that it has to end, all of it. We are peace activists as vegans.

And Watson could see that. Watson was a mountain climber, an organic vegan grower. Watson appreciated the outdoors and spent a lot of time there, appreciating free-living animals.

Watson revived a blackbird who hit a newly built glass wall, providing food and shelter, and the eye that appeared to be hanging from the socket by an inch-long stem when Watson found the bird—they [Donald and Dorothy] said we’ve never killed. And amazingly enough, because nature is amazing, it wasn’t long— George will remember how many days it was— the eye went back into the head, the little bird took off, and would dip every time Dorothy was out with the laundry.

Donald said this to George in an interview, during the sound check, and wanted this to be observed as part of the history of animals’ natural lives. Here was this animal who was healed, and appeared to signal gratitude. Watson wanted to say something about who other animals are.

What Donald and Dorothy did had nothing to do with domination; it was like pulling a child out of the way of traffic. It was control, but just enough to ensure the child lived and flourished. It was the power of love.[4]

[Applause.]

That’s very nice of everybody for staying. This will be posted on Abolitionist Online, the website. Claudette Vaughan, the editor, has asked for the transcript. You’ve made it special, and a really nice time for me, and, I’m sure, for a lot of people who will read the website.

 

Footnotes

 

  1. For related reading see the chapter by Richard Dawkins called “Gaps in the Mind” in The Great Ape Project (Cavalieri & Singer, eds.; St. Martin’s Griffin, 1993).

  2. Marine Animal Rescue merged with Friends of Animals in 2007, but separated from FRIENDS OF ANIMALS in 2013. I (Lee) WORKED WITH FRIENDS OF ANIMALS FROM 2002 to 2013.

  3. In Introduction to Animal Rights: Your Child or the Dog (Temple University Press, 2000), Francione states:

Most of us share the view that in situations of true conflict between human and animal interests, or in some emergency that requires us to make a choice between a human and an animal—that is, when it is necessary to do so—we ought to prefer the interests of a human over the interests of an animal.

Regarding such situations, Francione says (on page 159):

If we prefer the human over the animal in all such situations, are we not guilty of being speciesist in that our choice represents a morally unjustifiable prejudice against animals? No, no more than the physician who would always choose to give the one available pint of blood to the healthy human over the terminally ill one is guilty of prejudice against the terminally ill.

4. For a remarkable discussion related to this, which inspired me to understand Donald’s and Dorothy’s act in such a light, see Yi-Fu Tuan’s Dominance and Affection: The Making of Pets (Yale University Press; 1985)—as a whole, and particularly at page 176.